IPP 507: Environmental EthicsAWAYMAVE - The Distance Mode of MA in Values and the Environment at Lancaster University Block 4 - The Integrated Aesthetic |
|||
| AWAYMAVE
Home | 507 Home |
Aims and Outcomes | Module Description
| | Tutor Details | Biblio | Assessment | Resources | discussion | |
|||
Multi-sensuous Engagement and Disinterestedness
Suggested reading from Kemal and GaskellSee Arnold Berleant, ‘The Aesthetics of Art and Nature’ for criticisms of disinterestedness. Suggested further reading for this section: John A. Fisher, ‘What the Hills Are Alive With:
In Defense of the Sounds of Nature,’ Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, 56:2, 1998. In the last block we worked through a set of contemporary approaches to aesthetic appreciation of nature. Several problems were found in cognitive theories of aesthetic appreciation of nature, as put forward, mainly, by Carlson. Alternative approaches, without the necessary condition of science, presented a more open and richer account of appreciation. Here, I sketch out my own theory of aesthetic appreciation of nature, as set out in chapters 5 and 6 of Aesthetics of the Natural Environment. I call my aesthetic approach the ‘integrated aesthetic’. In the first section of these webnotes, we consider two components of the integrated aesthetic, multi-sensuous engagement and disinterestedness. In the second section, we look at three other components, imagination, emotion and the role of knowledge. Why an 'Integrated Aesthetic'?The integrated aesthetic is ‘integrated’ in the sense that I want to draw upon both the situation of the subject and the situation of the object for guiding appreciation. As I see it, appreciation comes about through the subject’s appreciative capacities – perception, imagination, and so on, coupled with open, sympathetic attention to qualities of the aesthetic object. Approaching the problem of appreciation in this way prevents leaning too heavily toward a subject-oriented or object-oriented account and captures the potential richness of as many relevant features as may be present in any particular encounter with an environment. My preference for ‘integration’ underscores how aesthetic appreciation of nature involves a relationship between appreciator and environment:
There is movement, new things to smell or see, and changes
in light, wind and temperature. The aesthetic situation reflects the complexity
of environmental appreciation, where appreciation is more like a happening,
and where that happening creates the conditions of the situation we are
in. In these relations, some distance is maintained, rather than our being fully integrated with the environment. Recognition of nature’s otherness is implicit in appreciation. More specifically, this is expressed through the concept of disinterestedness, which I put forward as one component of appreciation. Although inspired by Kant's use of the concept, I aim for a renewed understanding of disinterestedness, where its negative connotations are stripped away to reveal it as a concept that supports engagement and sympathetic attention. Disinterestedness also helps to filter out idiosyncratic features of the appreciator. In this respect, the integrated aesthetic falls short of embracing all aspects of the subject. Some aspects will not be given prominence mainly because they may idiosyncratic or not easily shared by others making aesthetic judgements of the same object. In this way, I distinguish aesthetic appreciation as a shared activity from the more private or personal activity of expressing preferences.
|
Now read chapter 6 of Aesthetics of the Natural Environment |
Noël Carroll: ‘On Being Moved By Nature: Between
Religion and Natural History’
R.W. Hepburn, ‘Trivial and serious in aesthetic appreciation of
nature’
Marcia Eaton, ‘Fact and Fiction in the Aesthetic
Appreciation of Nature’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
56:2, Spring 1998.
Thomas Heyd, ‘Aesthetic Appreciation and the Many Stories About
Nature’, British Journal of Aesthetics, vol. 41, 2001;
Jane Howarth, ‘Nature’s Moods’, British Journal
of Aesthetics, April 1995, pp. 108-120.
Both Kant and Hepburn argue that imagination has a significant role in aesthetic appreciation of nature. For Kant, imagination is central in aesthetic judgements of nature. It frees the mind up from the constraints of intellectual and practical interests and enables a play of associations and creative reflection in relation to nature’s qualities. Hepburn also wants to highlight imagination’s power, where it enables us to:
'shift attention flexibly from aspect to aspect of the natural objects before one, to shift focus from close-up to long shot, from textural detail to overall atmospheric haze or radiance; to overcome stereotyped grouping and clichéd ways of seeing.’ ('Contemporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural Beauty', p. 47).
Through imagination we can adopt several different perspectives, as well as entirely new ones. It gives us ways to reach beyond stereotyped modes of appreciating environments: to come afresh to familiar or everyday environments and to locate previously undiscovered qualities.
Thomas Heyd makes a similar point when he argues that we can overcome aesthetic boredom or fatigue ‘by increasing the contrast in our perceptual experience, and, generally, by enhancing the possibilities for the play of imagination’ (Heyd, ‘Aesthetic Appreciation and the Many Stories About Nature’, p. 130). This is partly achieved by integrating various non-scientific stories of the land into appreciation.
We can identify four ways in which imagination functions in aesthetic appreciation of nature: metaphorical imagination; exploratory imagination; projective imagination; ampliative imagination and revelatory imagination. I shall highlight three of them here.
Exploratory Imagination
Exploratory imagination is the most deeply tied to perception of the various modes we use. Here, imagination follows the lead of perception and explores the various perceptual qualities and relationships between qualities as we attend to the aesthetic object.
While perception does much of the work in simply taking in the various features of the object and cordoning it off in our perceptual field, imagination reaches beyond this in a free contemplation of the object.
As imagination brings meanings to bear on perceptual qualities, we identify aesthetic qualities and broaden our grasp of the object. In this way exploratory imagination helps the appreciator to make an initial discovery of aesthetic qualities.
Can you think of an example of exploratory imagination?
Projective Imagination
Projective imagination draws on imagination's projective powers. Projection involves imagining ‘on to’ what is perceived such that what is actually there is somehow replaced with or overlaid by a projected image. In visually exploring the stars at night, for example, imaginative activity overlays perception in attempting to unify the various forms traced by individual stars, perhaps by naturally projecting geometrical shapes onto them. Sometimes we take the further imaginative leap of projecting ourselves into natural objects and ‘scenes’.
[GARDEN Photo to be inserted
Caption: An example of invitation in gardens (see Stephanie Ross quotation in Aesthetics of the Natural Environment, p. 155).]
Can you think of other cases of projective imagination in which we project
ourselves into natural environments or objects?
Ampliative Imagination
The third mode of imaginative activity, ampliative imagination, involves the inventive powers of imagination, and need not make use of images. It is marked by heightened creative powers and a special curiosity in its response to natural objects.
Here imagination amplifies what is given in perception,
thereby reaching beyond the mere projection of images onto objects. This
activity is therefore more penetrative, resulting in a deeper imaginative
treatment of the object. It is imagination in its most active mode in
aesthetic experience.
In contemplating the smoothness of a sea pebble, I visualise the relentless
surging of the ocean as it has shaped the pebble into its worn form. I
might also imagine how it looked before it became so smooth, this image
contributing to my wonder and delight in the object. Merely thinking about
the pebble does not vivify the silky smoothness that is emphasised by
contrasting its feel with an image of its pre-worn state. Ampliative imagination
enables us to expand upon what we perceive by placing or contextualising
the aesthetic object with narrative images.
Can you think of an example of ampliative imagination?
Revelatory Imagination
Where ampliative imagination leads to disclosure or revelation, I call this imaginative activity 'revelatory'. In this mode, invention stretches the power of imagination to its limits, and this often gives way to new ideas and meanings; revelation in the non-religious sense.
Coming upon a huge landslide (or even a more modest pile of boulders at the bottom of a valley) may bring home in a deep way the tremendous power of natural forces - imagining and feeling that the earth is something that moves and shifts, even though we may stand quite solidly upon it. I also recall the first time I saw the Northern Lights. For me, it was certainly an experience of the sublime, and through it, I felt in a strong way the sense of earth being only one, insignificant part of a much greater galaxy (and universe).
Not all imaginative revelations are pleasant and positive. Imaginative engagement also reveals the horror and suffering of humanity and the natural world. Witnessing human evil, natural disasters, or even the everyday encounter of a cat stalking and killing a bird, strike imagination in ways that spread meaning more deeply, and in ways that also make these experiences more demanding and difficult to undergo.
Reining in Imagination
Imagination, rather like emotion, has had a rough ride in philosophy. Within aesthetics and the arts, it is heralded as the seat of artistic creativity and genius, however, outside aesthetics it is often derided as distracting us from truth and leading us into a world of fantasy.
This latter attitude seems to be implicit in some of the criticisms raised against imagination in aesthetic appreciation of nature. The main charge is that it sometimes leads us away from the object rather than towards it, and thus leads to inappropriate responses. When in its most fanciful mode, imagination may produce personal fantasies that distract attention from the aesthetic object, and possibly lead to trivialising and sentimentalising nature.
(This type of criticism is raised by Marcia Eaton, Ronald Moore and Robert Fudge. I discuss them at length and defend imagination against them in Aesthetics of the Natural Environment, pp. 161-170.)
We can identify three ways to understand how imagination is guided and works along 'rules of relevance' in aesthetic appreciation of nature:
(1) the way the object’s qualities evoke and
direct our imaginings - here imagination is guided through our perception
of various qualities in the object/environment.
(2) disinterestedness;
(3) imagining well, which is characterised by comparing imagination to
a virtue, so that we ‘imagine well’ when we use imagination
skilfully and appropriately according to the context of aesthetic appreciation.
The philosopher R.K. Elliott describes how we may focus on the aesthetic object while also using imagination to deepen our appreciation o fit (here he discusses this is relation to artworks):
'[Imagination] seems to have a double movement: an expansive moving out from the work along lines of relevance, and a turning back upon the work which concentrates the additional ideas or images around it like a nimbus. One might add that Imagination obeys not only a rule of relevance but a rule of decorum, for the rapt state would be at an end if a thought or image which was felt to belittle the work obtruded into it.'( R. K. Elliott, ‘Imagination in the Experience of Art’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, vol. six, 1971–1972: Philosophy and the Arts (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1974), p. 101)
You might like to have a look at the way Ronald Hepburn finds a medium between overly trivialising and overly serious aesthetic appreciation of nature in his 'Trivial and Serious in Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature'.
What do you think? Is imagination prone to overly humanising nature?
Emotion is a valuable resource in aesthetic appreciation but it too suffers from caricature: it is commonly viewed as too subjective and arbitrary to pin down as a legitimate part of appreciation. Any discussion of it needs to show not only how nature can evoke emotion and be expressive, but also give some assurance that emotion will not lead to wayward or distorting responses.
Recall that In his article, 'On Being Moved By Nature: Between Religion and Natural History', Noel Carroll addresses the specific problem of justifying emotional responses to nature, that is, the particular emotions we feel when we experience great waterfalls, richly textured mosses, or tiny spiders. Carroll's article is also worth a look for its criticisms of Carlson too. Carroll says that Carlson's 'natural environmental model' simply leaves no room for our emotional responses. I think he's right.
He adopts a cognitive theory of emotions and sets out to show how emotion can be an appropriate response to nature. An emotional response is appropriate or inappropriate according to its object and aspects of the subject having the emotion, including particular beliefs surrounding the object.
On Carroll’s view, justifying the feeling of excitement from the grandeur of a waterfall depends upon the qualities of the waterfall and the beliefs and thoughts that underlie the response. The thoughts and beliefs cannot be subjective, but rather must be reasonably shared by other people.
Using this strategy he shows how emotional responses are not subjective projections onto the landscape and how they relate to the whole aesthetic situation – subject, object and context.
You might wonder why Carroll sees himself as having to 'justify' emotional responses to nature. This is because he is conscious of the objectivist strategy of Carlson, and he is trying to show that something often viewed as deeply personal can none the less have objective import. This becomes important in trying to show that emotional responses to nature have importance beyond ourselves and ought to be taken seriously (that's assuming we want them to be taken seriously beyond ourselves, e.g., in cases where our responses may have a role in fighting to conserve some natural area.)
Exercise
In what ways have you been moved by nature? What is the range of emotions you have felt? You might jot them down. Do you think the range is as wide as it is in the appreciation of artworks (music, film, novels, visual art, etc.)?
Scientific knowledge
Remember that Carlson believes that scientific knowledge is a necessary condition of appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature. In my approach, scientific knowledge may have a role, as fed into our aesthetic experiences of nature. It may even deepen and expand our aesthetic appreciation. But the integrated aesthetic does not make such knowledge a necessary or even important part of aesthetic experience.
I have to admit that after writing the book, I am inclined to agree that there will be some cases where we will need some knowledge of a scientific sort in order to properly appreciate something (but not in all cases)!!. This is especially true in cases of so-called unscenic nature. A dull-looking bog may become beautiful if we are given knowledge of its various species and its history (here imagination may step in to reconstruct its history). It is perhaps true that if we spent enough time there without that knowledge we could come to experience its beauty, but I'm not sure.
A Pluralist View of Knowledge
Carlson thinks that the main legitimate source of knowledge for aesthetic appreciation of nature is scientific knowledge (recently he seems to be allowing in some other forms such as indigenous knowledge). But people like myself, Thomas Heyd, and others, adopt a more pluralistic stance toward knowledge. There can be many stories about nature, and many of them will give us rich, appropriate (non-wayward) ways of grasping and valuing nature's qualities.
An example I use back in Chapter 3 of the book may be of interest here:
In the Nordic environment of Finland, the word for the Aurora Borealis is ‘revontulet’, which means ‘fox fires’. It is said to derive from old folklore that explains the bright, pulsating, red and blue lights as the painterly effects of the arctic fox’s bushy tail, which starts fires and sprays snow into the night sky. (Recounted by Joe Brady in ‘Aurora Borealis: The Northern Lights’, http://virtual.finland.fi/finfo/english/aurora_borealis.html . This is the original source but unfortunately this link on the web no longer works).
Through another story, the story of science, the colours of the Aurora Borealis take on another meaning . We see them not as the fiery art of the arctic fox, but rather as caused by solar winds moving across the upper atmosphere and hitting gas molecules, which creates light. The colours are not the fox’s chosen palate, but rather they correspond to the colours of gases in the ionosphere.
In the interpretation of the Aurora Borealis, both folklore and science provide acceptable interpretations; they give alternative ways of seeing the spectacular show in the sky. If the point were simply to understand the phenomenon before us, with knowledge as the aim, the scientist would give us the fullest factual explanation. But here, we are talking about aesthetic appreciation, and that is something quite different.
Local Knowledge
Local knowledge can be described as a type of common sense knowledge, which is based in the experience of a place and local practices in relation to the land - experiences which may also have a strong aesthetic element. It has an important role to play in environmental policy-making, since public consultation is becoming more and more important. (This doesn't mean that these days such knowledge always wins over expert knowledge!)
For some interesting examples of local knowledge, see the following:
Richard Mabey's ongoing project to develop a Birds Britannica, compiled using many contributions from the public (similar to his already published Flora Britannica):
http://www.randomhouse.co.uk/birdsbritannica/
Another favourite of mine is the ‘Biodiversity Stories’ website, sponsored by Scottish Natural Heritage and the Royal Botanic Gardens Edinburgh, which brings together in one place a range of knowledges about species and habitats and our cultural relationship to them. The public is invited to contribute audio and text-based stories about the wildlife, ecology and landscapes of Scotland, with folktales, old legends, poems, ecological accounts and stories about practical uses of nature.
http://www.biodiversitystories.co.uk
Exercise:
Do you know of a case from environmental conservation where local knowledge has played an important role? How would aesthetic experience have been involved in that knowledge? If so, why not share it with others through the discussion site.
Emily Brady, November 2003