Away MAVEThe Distance Mode of MA in Values and the Environment at Lancaster University Block 5: Science, Deliberation and Democracy. |
|||
|Home|Aims and Outcomes|Module Description|Tutor Details|Biblio|Assessment|Resources|Discussion|
IntroductionOne of the central arguments for deliberative democracy
in the policy world has been the decline of trust in scientific experts
and the legitimacy of political decisions arrived at by technocratic means.
Exercise On what grounds do the authors of this paper suggest there has been a decline of public trust in science? Is that claim defensible? If there has been a decline of trust is that decline in trust warranted or is science still worthy of trust in our deliberations? How if at all could deliberative institutions address those problems of trust? While deliberative democracy is sometimes presented as a response to the problem of a decline in trust in scientific experts, the existence of expertise also raises a problem for deliberative theories of democracy. Public decisions in the modern world rely on claims by experts the grounds for which are often opaque to direct inspection by the citizen and indeed by other scientists. Nor is this opacity eliminable. The capacity to make and evaluate particular claims in the special sciences relies on a background of training within particular scientific practices. It relies on particular competences and know-how not all of which is open to explicit articulation. Both citizen and scientist in most matters rely on the competences of others which they lack. Habermas’s assumption of equality of competence that is built into the model of communicative rationality fails to acknowledge the existence of epistemic inequality even in the ideal conditions of his non-coercive speech community. In this block we consider these problems in more detail. Background ProblemI want to start by considering a typical radio phone in around issues of health or environmental risks in the UK. For example, listening to one of the many radio phone-ins that took place in the wake of the BSE scare in the UK, one standard and quite understandable worry expressed in the circumstance runs like this. Some caller had just had a weekend listening to a series of scientific experts who have argued intensely with each other about the links between BSE and CJD, some saying on the one hand that there is no proof that any relation exists and some claiming on the other that there is a major health risk which is only just beginning to unfold. The caller complains: 'I just don't know who to believe. Who do I trust?'. It is a standard response to a large number of environmental problems, which involve scientific expertise and are subject to controversy.
How would you respond to the caller?
Consider again Kant's account of the enlightenment.
Given Kant's account what reply to the caller would be appropriate? Would that Kantian account differ from your own?
|
For a useful bibliography on the role of testimony
in the justification of knowledge claims see: http://ucsu.colorado.edu/~brindell/soc-epistemology/Bibliographies/Testimony/testimony.htm |
The phone-in caller's problem is not one of addressing the arguments offered but making a judgement about who is credible and trustworthy - who should be believed. The problem of who to believe becomes central. But it is not clear how one is to make judgements.
The importance of judgements of credibility to knowledge claims is one that is recognised by Aristotle in the Rhetoric. He notes that credibility has both epistemological dimensions - the speaker must have good sense and be reliable in the formation of judgements - and ethical dimensions - the speaker must have the moral character that allows us to trust their utterance and there must be grounds for believing that they are not inclined to impart falsehoods to their audience:
False statements and bad advice are due to one or more of the following three causes. Men either from a false opinion through want of good sense; or they form a true opinion, but because of their moral badness do not say what they really think; or finally, they are both sensible and upright, but not be well disposed to their hearers...
The recognition of the role of authority, credibility
and testimony in the justification of knowledge claims is one that is
central to some recent sociology of science.
Shapin for example characterises the sociology of scientific knowledge
as involving the rejection of the following view.
The credibility and the validity [sic.] of a proposition ought to be one and the same. Truth shines by its own lights...Once upon a time...students of sciences...believed that truth was its own recommendation, or if not that, something very like it. If one wanted to know, and one rarely did, why it was that true propositions were credible, one was referred back to their truth, to the evidence for them, or to those methodical procedures the unambiguous following of which testified to the truth of the product. (Shapin, S. 1995 'Cordelia's Love: Credibility and the Social Studies of Science' Perspectives on Science, 3, 255-275)
Once it is admitted that the issue is one of credibility of knowledge-claims and not their truth, then it is quite proper to point to the variety of social causes of credibility or even, if one wants to use the language, their social construction.
It does not follow that truth or knowledge are thereby social constructions unless one already accepts a naive cognitivist identification of credibility and truth.
Neither does it follow that credibility is a sufficient
condition of knowledge or that it is a necessary condition - that 'no
credibility, no knowledge'.
Shapin also defines truth to mean 'warranted assertability'
or 'accepted truth' (Shapin A Social History of Truth 4) Shapin
allows that there is a 'restrictive notion of truth' beloved by philosophers
that insists on a distinction between locally accepted belief and truth.
This is not a restrictive philosopher's concept but a basic requirement
of any defensible account of truth. Shapin's book A Social History
of Truth is mis-titled: it as an excellent social history of credible
belief.
Latour and Woolgar in Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts also note that reference to character has a place in science: data in science is accepted or rejected on the basis of evaluation of those who produced it:
reference to the human agency involved in the production of statements was very common. Indeed, it was clear from participants' discussions that who had made the claim was as important as the claim itself. In a sense, these discussions constituted a complex sociology and psychology of science engaged in by the participants themselves. (Latour and Woolgar 1979, 164)
This is I am sure true. However, none of the anti-realist and strong constructionist conclusions that Latour and Woolgar take to follow from that observation do so.
What recent work in the sociology of knowledge does highlight is the institutional dimension to judgements of credibility in science. Classical discussions of credibility, like that of Aristotle, focused on judgements about the epistemic and moral virtues and vices of individuals. We live in a world in which testimony is offered to us by strangers, by ‘spokespersons’ and ‘experts’, who call upon us to believe what they say on the basis of certification from institutions - academic, industrial, commercial and political. The different institutional dimensions of evaluation are of significance here. What institutions deserve epistemological trust in what conditions?
'Democracy...is a continual struggle between the expert... and the common man...Our life is connected more and more with experts, but on the other hand, we are less prepared to accept other people’s judgements, when making decisions' (Otto Neurath 'Visual Education')
Habermas's account of discourse ethics and public deliberation belongs to the Kantian tradition. To engage in reasoned dialogue is to aim not at compromise but on convergence in judgements. The activity of argument presupposes an ideal of free agreement in judgement founded on good reason: in ideal discourse ‘no force except that of the better argument is exercised’. Habermas echoes Kant's account of the role of reason in public life: ‘For reason has no dictatorial authority; its verdict is always simply the agreement of free citizens, of whom each one must be permitted to express, without let or hindrance, his objections or even his veto.’ That account assumes in the background an assumption of epistemic equality. In the ideal speech situation all participants are equally competent to make and assess validity claims for different speech acts.
A potential problem with Habermas's account is that the assumptions of epistemic equality even in an ideal speech situation might look too strong. Given the division of knowledge in society, different groups of individuals will not have the same competence to judge the validity of claims. Different individuals enter debates with distinct competences. Without a great deal of training in special sciences, I will not be in a position to make any judgement about the details of evidence in a scientific dispute. Habermas’ account is forced to gloss over some of the real difficulties about the role of science in modern public life, in particular that of simultaneous reliance on expertise coupled with proper scepticism about its claims. This failure borders on the paradoxical in that the application of Habermasian account of communicative rationality are often in just those areas where this problem is most acute.
The Habermasian model of communicative rationality has had particular influence in the recent revival of the theory of deliberative democracy and the practice which it informs. However, experiments in deliberative democracy inspired by it highlight a problem in the model’s account of the role of science in public life. Many of the experiments in various new deliberative institutions such as citizens’ juries and citizens’ panels have had their application in areas of public policy which involve scientific expertise which is the subject of internal and external controversy. Indeed what is taken to be a problem of a decline in public trust in scientific expertise forms the starting point of many practical applications of deliberative institutions, particularly those applied to risk.
In actual citizens' juries in which scientific evidence is introduced, participants - like members of actual juries in court cases - do not consider the evidence directly. They judge the credibility of the persons who present that evidence. Are there good reasons to believe those persons? It might be that on this judgement, we can assume a rough equality of competence at least in ideal conditions. It may be that we need some less intellectualist account of what our competences in democracy need to look like.
I introduced the problems that testimony and authority in the context of conservative criticism of the enlightenment ideal. However, there is no reason to assume that any of the points we have been considering have a necessary relation to conservatism or that the enlightenment ideal cannot be rescued. Can the ideal be salvaged?
One possible response is to perform a radical inversion of the conservative view which undermines the enlightenment model from the more radical side of the critics of the enlightenment.
The fact that all practices rely upon authority shows that all appeals to reason independent of social authority are simply disguised ways of enforcing social power. The appeal to reason is just the way another group realises power. Hence the rhetorical analysis of science that aim to deflate the appeals to reason.
Problems for caller: leads to generalised scepticism that is unable to make any distinction about who is to believed.
An alternative is to redefine our account of the enlightenment ideal that allows for less heady picture of maturity that is more akin to the skills an agent in a public forum requires.
a) Distinction between epistemological authority and social authority - being an authority and being in authority (In Ecology, Policy and Politics I make the distinction between internal and external authority.)
'But I hear on all sides the cry: Don't argue! The officer says: Don't argue, get on parade! The tax-official: Don't argue, pay! The clergyman: Don't argue, believe!...The public use of man's reason must always be free, and it alone can bring enlightenment among men...' (Kant 'What is Enlightenment?')
Given an imperative 'Do X', there are two answers that a
person might make to the response 'Why?':
(1) 'Because I am your teacher, your manager, your priest, paying you,
etc';
(2) 'Because X would be the right thing to do, is the best thing to do,
is a valid inference, etc.'
The first set of responses make essential reference to the individual's occupancy of a particular institutional position or status. Call on social authority.
The second set of responses make no call on institutional positions of authority, but, rather, on standards independent of institutional positions and personal qualities. The responses call only on such impersonal standards. One accepts the answers only if one believes the person has the capacities of judgement to make such a call on these standards. Call on standards independent of institutional. position
Restatement of the enlightenment ideal: Deference to the judgements of a person the grounds of which one is not oneself able to appraise is rational only if there are good reasons to believe they meets some standards independent of institutional position. Or to make the same point in a negative way, persons' possessions of external goods as such - their occupancy of institutional positions, their possession of wealth - are never good grounds for yielding one's own judgement to theirs. (Compare Habermas's ideal speech situation)
Two qualifications:
I. In practice the distinction is less clearly distinct: some institutional positions are granted in recognition of a persons competence in an activity by peers in that activity e.g. doctors, scientists etc. But the only grounds for accepting judgements is the belief they could be redeemed by the standards themselves. Their mere occupancy of those positions cannot count.
II. Appeal to standards that are independent of institutional position is a necessary condition of rational deference to an authority. However, it is not a sufficient condition. Some practices themselves are 'bogus'. They issue in claims which are false, develop ways of 'seeing' which are forms of blindness, develop dispositions of character which are vices. It is this that provides the component of the enlightenment legacy that ought to be accepted. That the enlightenment theorist might have appealed to individual reason does not entail that much of the enlightenment critique of superstition and of the bogus forms of authority it supported was not in order. This enlightenment critique of particular social practices and traditions is itself proper. So also are some of the tools and skills of suspicion it employed, not least their universal tools of logic and the analytical skills required for their employment. Practices themselves form quite proper objects of criticism. They can, and often do, act as masks for particular interests - for arbitrary power and unfounded barriers to professions.
a. Independence of knowledge and political and economic power - worries about the commercialisation of science
b. Epistemic case for social equality: a rough equality in power and wealth is a condition for rational acceptance of authoritative judgements
These need to be wider than those of 'pure reason' to which Kantian models of the enlightenment sometimes appear to appeal. As we noted above in the modern world the issue of credible testimony has an institutional and political focus. We live in a world in which testimony is offered to us by strangers, by 'spokespersons' and 'experts', who call upon us to believe what they say on the basis of certification from institutions - academic, industrial, commercial and political. The different institutional dimensions of evaluation are of significance here. What institutions deserve epistemological trust in what conditions? What is required as an answer is not a series of decision rules but a political epistemology concerning conditions of trust, and a corresponding social and political theory about its institutional preconditions. The association of evaluative practices with positions of social power and wealth for example induces quite proper scepticism about its reliability. Indeed, there is I believe a good epistemological argument for social and political equality founded upon conditions of trust. In the absence of ideal conditions we require tools to scrutinise institutions.
Caller: one actual reply to caller worried about who to
trust on BSE:
Don't trust those who have an axe to grind those who are tied to the food
industry and attempt to reassure you. Seek those who are independent.
And remember there is a difference between not proving there is a connection
between BSE and CJD and proving there is no connection.
The arguments make no mention of evidence for or against the connection. They give good rules of thumb about who to trust and how to interrogate arguments with some general principles of good reasoning. It calls upon an understanding of the conditions in which trust in the authoritative utterances of others is rational and tools of proper scepticism. They are the tools of scepticism that are employed in citizens’ juries where they interrogate the testimony of experts.
The problem with Kantian picture of the mature agent does not lie in the values of the enlightenment, in particular that of autonomy. It lies in a particular conception of reasoned deliberation and epistemological maturity which denies that there is ever an occasion for accepting claims on testimony or authority (O’Neill, 1998a, ch.7). In its place one has a less heady picture of maturity that is more akin to the skills an agent in a public forum requires. She is able to reason well for herself, but knows when her own reason is insufficient; she is not credulous nor willing to accept all and any propositions put to her by putative authorities; she is able to judge whose testimony is reliable, whose is not; she knows when and how to be suspicious - she is versed in the practical art of suspicion. The skills of the mature autonomous agent are not, on this account, merely those of the good logician - although these are necessary. They are those of the person who knows when and where it is reasonable to trust claims that call on epistemic authority.