|Home|Aims
and Outcomes|Module
Description|Tutor
Details|Biblio|Assessment|Resources|Discussion|
From instrumental to communicative rationality
Habermas, in his response to Marcuse, rejects Marcuse's
criticisms of science as such. What he accepts is his criticism of scientism,
the claim that science alone embodies standards of reasoned discourse.
The problem in modern society is that instrumental action associated with
science is extended beyond its appropriate domain. The result is the reduction
of political and ethical life to the application of instrumental reason
for the realisation of 'non-rational ends' - a scientisation of society
founded upon an ideology of 'scientism' that only science gives knowledge.
What has to be resisted is the colonisation of the life-world by instrumental
reason. In particular his account is aimed against a technocratic conception
of political life.
To make good this claim Habermas has to show that identification
of reason with instrumental reason is a mistake - that there are forms
of public rationality other than instrumental rationality.
Think
for a moment
What makes for rational public deliberation?
Habermas's answer runs roughly as follows:
dialogue is rational to the extent it is free from the exercise
of power and strategic action, such that the judgements of participants
converge only under the authority of the good argument - ‘no force
except that of the better argument is exercised’ (Habermas, The
Legitimation Crisis of Late Capitalism 1975, p.108).
Public deliberation is to be governed by the standards of
communicative rationality.
In this block we examine this Habermas's account of public deliberation
in more detail. In the final block we will consider issues around the
relation of democracy, science and environmental policy.
Communicative action
Habermas's later work starts with a basic distinction between
communicative action which is consent orientated aims at arriving at mutual
understanding and purposive-rational action which is success orientated
and aims at arriving at the best mean to achieve some end. Habermas distinguishes
between two kinds of purposive-rational action
- Instrumental actions - actions orientated to some goal
in the physical world and which are judged by norms of efficiency
- Strategic actions - action that aims at influencing
other persons with the aim of achieving some end.
Communicative action: His account is based on the theory
of speech-acts developed by Austin and Searle.
The basics of Habermas's approach runs something as follows.
Different kinds of utterances require different kinds of validity claims.
- Constatives - make claims to truth: e.g. 'I assert the
window is open '. The aim of the utterance is to represent a state of
affairs. A criticism of this utterance will dispute the truth-claim
made. To agree with the utterance is to accept the truth of what the
speakers say - 'yes it is open'.
- Regulatives - make claims to normative rightness: e.g.
'I request you open the window', 'you ought to open the window'. The
aim of the utterance is to establish social co-ordination or relations
between social actors. A criticism of the utterance will dispute the
normative appropriateness or rightness of the offer or demand made by
the utterance. To accept the claim is to accept its appropriateness.
- Expressives - make claims to sincerity or truthfulness:
e.g. 'I wish the window was open'. The aim of the utterance is to express
a subjective experience, feeling or desire. To criticise the claim is
to question the sincerity of the speaker. To accept the claim is to
accept the sincerity of the speaker.
In each case part of understanding a speech act is knowing
what validity claim it is making: ‘we understand a speech-act when
we know what makes it acceptable’.
Exercise
Think of examples of constative, regulative and
expressive utterances. What kinds of question might a person make in challenging
the validity of those claims? How would you defend those claims against
those challenges? What would be required to redeem the validity claim?
Please send some examples to the discussion site.
Ideal speech situation
To make an utterance is to implicitly raise a validity claim:
to truth, to normative rightness or to sincerity. One must in principle
be able to redeem or make good those claims. What are the conditions required
to make good those claims? The are claims one could redeem in an ideal
speech situation.
The ideal speech situation represents the conditions required
to arrive at communicative agreement or understanding.
1. Every speaker with competence to speak and act is
allowed to take part in a discourse
2. a. Everyone is allowed to question any assertion whatever.
b. Everyone is allowed to introduce any assertion whatever into the
discourse.
c. Everyone is allowed to express his/her attitudes, desires and needs
3. No speaker may be prevented, by internal or external coercion, form
exercising the rights laid down in 1 and 2.
In the ideal speech situation the only force is the force
of the better argument.
This ideal is assumed by speakers and hearers in making and interpreting
utterances.
It is also a regulative ideal that can be used in the criticism of the
course of actual discourse.
Communicative rationality
The ideal speech situation defines the standards of communicative
rationality (as against instrumental rationality.)
Here is Dryzek's useful summary of the idea of communicative
rationality:
Communicative rationality clearly obtains to the degree
social action is free from domination (the exercise of power), strategizing
by the actors involved, and (self-) deception. Further, all actors
should be equally and fully capably of making and questioning arguments
(communicatively competent). There should be no restrictions on the
participation of these competent actors. Under such conditions, the
only remaining authority is that of a good argument, which can be
advanced on behalf of the veracity of empirical description, the understanding,
and, equally important, the validity of normative judgements. (Dryzek,
J. (1990) Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy and Political
Science, p.15)
Discourse ethics
Habermas argues that from these presuppositions of argumentation
and communication in the moral domain we can derive the following principle
of discourse ethics:
Principle of universalisability
Every valid norm must satisfy the condition that all affected
can accept the consequences and the side effects its general observance
can be anticipated to have for the satisfaction of everyone’s interests
(and these consequences are preferred to those of known alternative possibilities).
(Habermas The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity p. 65)
Features of discourse ethics:
1. Cognitivist: Habermas's discourse ethic is cognitivist.
That is, it holds that ethical claims are a matter of judgement and belief
that are open to rational deliberation. Habermas rejects the non-congitivist
view that ethical claims are simply the expression of the attitudes, preferences
or emotions of the speaker, in part because he holds that would take morality
out of the realm of reasoned discussion. However, while Habermas holds
that moral claims are open to rational deliberation, he is not a moral
realist. He rejects the claim that moral utterances are true or false
in the way that constative or assertive utterances do. They rather make
validity claims that are 'analogous' to the validity claims of truth.
What matters for Habermas is not the truth of moral claims but their being
open to reasoned deliberation.
2. Formalistic: Habermas's discourse ethic is formalistic:
it does not state any substantive moral norms. Rather it offers a formal
procedure which any norm must satisfy if it is to be morally acceptable.
It is a procedural theory.
3. Priority of the right over the good: Related to the
last point, Habermas like many other contemporary philosophers influenced
by Kant, hold that basic moral principles must not presuppose any particular
conception of the good life. The claim commits Habermas to a particular
form of liberalism that holds that the basic principles of justice that
govern public life should be neutral between different conceptions of
the good life. That neutrality is required by the diversity and pluralism
of ethical outlooks in modern societies. Given the existence of a plurality
of different conceptions of what it is to live a good life one requires
public procedures for conversation which are themselves neutral between
competing conceptions of the good life. Larmore offers the following useful
account of 'universal norm of rational conversation' that attempts to
capture Habermas's argument for political neutrality.
When two people disagree about some specific point,
but wish to continue talking about the general problem they wish to
solve, each should prescind from the belief that the other rejects,
(1) in order to construct an argument on the basis of his other beliefs
that will convince the other of the disputed belief, or (2) in order
to shift to another aspect of the problem, where the possibilities
of agreement seem greater. In the face of disagreement, those who
wish to continue the conversation should retreat to neutral ground,
with the hope of either resolving the dispute or by passing it. (Larmore,
C. (1987) Patterns of Moral Complexity p.53)
Exercise:
1. Before going on to the next section consider what kinds of procedures
or movements would best realise Habermas's ideal of public deliberation
in modern societies? In particular, what implications would they have
for deliberation about environmental matters?
2. Are there any features of Habermas's discourse ethics that would make
it either problematic or useful for environmental concerns?
Your answers to these really do need to go to the discussion
site so that we can continue the conversation there.
One issue that might have concerned you is how those
who cannot speak - non-humans or future generations - enter into Habermas's
account of ethics.
Deliberative democracy
Enlightenment and the public use of reason
Habermas's account of communicative rationality has its
roots in the Kantian model of the enlightenment. Consider again Kant's
description of the enlightenment which we discussed in block one.
Kant ‘What is enlightenment?’
Enlightenment is man's emergence from his self-incurred
immaturity. Immaturity is the inability to use one's own understanding
without the guidance of another. The immaturity is self-incurred if
its cause is not lack of understanding, but lack of resolution and
courage to use it without the guidance of another. The motto of the
enlightenment is therefore: Sapere aude! Have courage to use your
own understanding...For enlightenment of this kind, all that is needed
is freedom. And the freedom in question is the most innocuous form
of all - freedom to make public use of one's reason in all matters.
But I hear on all sides the cry: Don't argue! The officer says: Don't
argue, get on parade! The tax-official: Don't argue, pay! The clergyman:
Don't argue, believe!...The public use of man's reason must always
be free, and it alone can bring enlightenment among men... (Kant 'An
Answer to the Question "What is enlightenment?"')
Autonomy: The ideal of maturity is closely related to that
of autonomy. The heteronomous character is one who lacks maturity, who
is willing to let his own judgement and understanding be guided by others
and who lacks the capacity, desire or courage to exercise them for himself.
To be autonomous is to have maturity and courage in using one's own understanding
and judgement.
For Kant to be autonomous is to be guided by reason: ‘For
reason has no dictatorial authority; its verdict is always simply the
agreement of free citizens, of whom each one must be permitted to express,
without let or hindrance, his objections or even his veto.’ (Kant
(1933) A738/B766.)
Enlightenment requires institutions that embody free public
dialogue.
Institutionalising public reason:
Habermas's account of communicative rationality has been
one important source of the recent revival of deliberative models of democracy.
A. Deliberative model democracy: democracy as a forum
through which judgements and preferences are transformed through reasoned
dialogue between free and equal citizens.
The deliberative model of democracy contrasts with the following
model democracy.
B. Economic model of democracy: democracy is a procedure
for aggregating and effectively meeting the given preferences of individuals.
Through votes individuals are able to record their preferences.
Against that model the deliberative account argues that
preferences are not given, but open to transformation through reasoned
dialogue.
Policy practice: formal policy practice has seen the
development of a variety of 'new' formal deliberative institutions which
have been introduced alongside 'older' democratic institutions and which
are often presented as experiments in deliberative democracy. These include
- citizens' juries,
- citizens' panels,
- consensus conferences,
- mediation panels,
- focus groups,
- in depth discussion groups
- round tables.
Application to environmental issues:
Both the theory and practice of deliberative democracy have
been particularly developed in the environmental sphere. A great deal
of recent work on environmental politics has been concerned with elaborating
a defence of deliberative approaches to our environmental problems. Environmental
conflicts are open to reasoned debate and judgement which aim to change
preferences not record them, it follows that different institutional forms
are required for their resolution. Since conflict is open to reasoned
adjudication, discursive institutions are the appropriate form for conflict
resolution.
Similarly environmental policy has been a prominent site
for the development of new experiments in deliberative democracy like
citizens’ juries, focus groups and consensus conferences.
Reading 1
For a classic and interesting example of how such
procedures might operate in practice see the following case study
about the siting of a waste disposal site in Switzerland:
http://www.piercelaw.edu/risk/vol7/spring/renn.htm
Reading 2
A good recent book on deliberative democracy as
applied to environmental issues is G. Smith (2003) Deliberative
Democracy and the Environment (Routledge).”
|
Problems for the deliberative theories of democracy
How far these experiments meet the ideal of deliberative
democracy is an open question. Here are some possible problems.
1. The distribution of voice:
Within deliberative fora voice can be unevenly distributed.
The capacity and confidence to speak and to be heard, differs across class,
gender and ethnicity.
2. Nature of deliberative process: the politics of controlled
conversations
Who controls?
- the space in which deliberation takes place
- constituency of deliberation - who is included
- the agenda on which participants are brought together
- the opening and closure of conversation
- the identities which participants are ascribed
- the afterlife of the results of deliberation and their
effects on policy making
3. Strategic use of deliberative institutions.
- Political use of focus groups to anticipate and close
public deliberation
- Corporate use of stakeholder engagement to disaggregate
the different actors in communities, to create local alliances and
to use local alliances against larger environmental regulation
A deliberative response:
The deliberative theorist can respond that these are internal
problems in practice that the deliberative theory of democracy is able
to itself to make. It is against the ideal of communicative rationality
that the potential failings of experiments in deliberative democracy are
judged. While 'the actual course of the debates deviates form the ideal
procedures of deliberative politics...presuppositions of rational discourse
have a steering effect on the course of the debates' (Habermas Between
Facts and Norms p.540)
Science, deliberation and democracy
One of the central arguments for deliberative democracy
in the policy world has been the decline of trust in scientific experts
and the legitimacy of political decisions arrived at by technocratic means.
Exercise
On what grounds do the authors of this paper suggest
there has been a decline of public trust in science? Is that claim defensible?
If there has been a decline of trust is that decline in trust warranted
or is science still worthy of trust in our deliberations? How if at all
could deliberative institutions address those problems of trust?
While deliberative democracy is sometimes presented as a
response to the problem of a decline in trust in scientific experts, the
existence of expertise also raises a problem for deliberative theories
of democracy. Public decisions in the modern world rely on claims by experts
the grounds for which are often opaque to direct inspection by the citizen
and indeed by other scientists. Nor is this opacity eliminable. The capacity
to make and evaluate particular claims in the special sciences relies
on a background of training within particular scientific practices. It
relies on particular competences and know-how not all of which is open
to explicit articulation. Both citizen and scientist in most matters rely
on the competences of others which they lack. Habermas’s assumption
of equality of competence that is built into the model of communicative
rationality fails to acknowledge the existence of epistemic inequality
even in the ideal conditions of his non-coercive speech community.
In the next block we consider these problems in more detail.
Block 4 by John O'Neill
|