Away MAVEThe Distance Mode of MA in Values and the Environment at Lancaster University Block 3: Marcuse, Habermas, and Science as Ideology |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|Home|Aims and Outcomes|Module Description|Tutor Details|Biblio|Assessment|Resources|Discussion|
Ideology and science: an overviewThe readings for this Block give us an opportunity to look
in more depth at the group of ideas about the science/nature question
that, to a certain extent, have shaped many of the approaches that have
been developed. If you have access to texts with general material on the
Frankfurt School or critical theory you will find it helpful to look at
those as well. A Note on Ideology Before embarking on the writings of Marcuse and Habermas
let's take a moment to (re)aquaint ourselves with the term 'ideology'.
Originally it meant the science of ideas, but the writers we will be looking
at use the term as developed by Marx to describe a set of ideas that is
in error, but accepted for specific reasons.
To be false it has to be the case that it is not true. To be functional it has to maintain a set of relations or class interests. To seem natural it usually fits with the way society has developed, so not any false idea can be ideological, it should seem reasonable to believe it and be misguided. Being 'natural' in this way helps to explain why the upholders of a particular ideology do not see themselves as, e.g., supporting an unfair status quo for their own benefit.
|
Please now read the first piece of set reading
for this block. This is Marcuse’s ‘From Negative to Positive
Thinking: Technological Rationality and the Logic of Domination’,
ch. 6 of One Dimensional Man [1964]. This is available online at: http://cartoon.iguw.tuwien.ac.at/christian/marcuse/odm6.html |
Exercise
After reading Marcuse can you think of a current response to an environmental problem that could be characterised as 'one-dimensional thinking?
Science is necessarily committed to an exploitative view
of nature and humans: Science has built into its concepts and methods
an interest in instrumental action, in the technical manipulation and
control of nature.
In his own words:
The science of nature develops under the technological a priori which projects nature as potential instrumentality, stuff of control and organization. And the apprehension of nature as (hypothetical) instrumentality precedes the development of all particular organization. One-Dimensional Man p.126
The point which I am trying to make is that science, by virtue of its own method and concepts, has projected and promoted a universe in which the domination of nature has remained linked to the domination of man - a link that tends to be fatal to this universe as a whole. Ibid. p.135
Marcuse rejects here the 'misuse model' of the application of science to the exploitation of humans and nature, i.e., the view that science is value free and has objective theories about the world that are subsequently used for independently defined ends. The technical manipulation of nature is itself held to be a form of domination, a domination that is linked with the technological domination of humans by others. The use of science in the destruction of the environment, in the development technology by the military and other forces of social control, in the rationalization of the political domain and so on are not 'abuses that arise at the level of their application'. Rather, the interest in domination enters their very construction, their methods and concepts.
The general outline of Marcuse's position can be stated as follows:
1. Modern natural science is necessarily committed to a view of nature as an object to be manipulated and controlled.
2. A science of humans based on the model of the natural sciences is thereby committed to the same view of humans.
3. Thus there is a necessary relation between the scientific domination of nature and the scientific domination of humans.
4. Modern natural science is historically specific and not the only form that science can take.
5. The liberation of both humans and nature requires a new science and technology grounded in a different interest, and with a different view of nature, not as an object to be manipulated but as "a totality of life to be protected and cultivated" (Counter-Revolution and Revolt p.61.). This change in the aims of science carries with it changes in its content:
Its hypotheses, without losing their rational character, would develop in an essentially different experimental context (that of a pacified world); consequently, science would arrive at essentially different concepts of nature and establish essentially different facts. One-Dimensional Man p.136
Central argument:
1. Historically there have been different conceptions of explanation associated
with different ontologies of nature. Eg. Prior to the scientific revolution
there was Aristotelian world-view in which teleological explanation was
central and the cosmos was seen as a goal directed whole.
2. What we now regard as science is an historically and
culturally specific phenomenon that emerged in the 16th and 17th centuries
- Galilean science.
This science was not just a product of applying rational empirical methods
to the study of nature , but rather defining nature in such a way that
these methods could be applied. These methods are related to a 'technological
a priori' - an interest in technical control.
3. Central to Galilean science is the distinction between
(real) primary and (unreal) secondary qualities. However, this is not
a 'discovery' about the way reality is, but rather a way of defining what
is 'real'.
Basis of the distinction:
a. what is real is defined as that which can be measured and hence appear
in mathematically specifiable laws of nature;
b. the reason one wants mathematically specifiable laws is that enables
us to make predictions about properties in nature that can be manipulated
and hence to control nature;
c thus, 'nature' is being defined so as to include only those properties
that can be treated in this way - it is constituted by an interest in
technical control.
4. Since science is constituted by an interest in technical control it is not an accident or 'misuse' of a value-neutral science that it is thus used when applied to nature and humans. Science is not value-neutral but constituted by certain values.
5. The liberation of nature and humans will be linked to
the creation of a new science constituted by different interests - nature
as a totality of life to be protected.
It is crucial to understanding Marcuse's position that we understand him
to be using 'reason' in two ways: sometimes to describe the kind of positivist
reason that he wishes to attack and sometimes to point to the necessary
role of reason, used in freedom, to criticise social norms such as an
instrumental science, and to show the means to reinstate questions of
human values.
Modern science develops a view of human reason and knowledge that subverts the notion of Reason (capital R) according to which one can have rational discourse about ethical and political ends.
1. The appeal to Husserl:
a. Marcuse misinterprets Husserl - especially on the 'technisation' of
science: for Husserl this concerns the formalisation of science not a
commitment to technical control. Husserl is talking about mathematics
as technique and Marcuse takes him to mean technology.
b. Husserl's arguments against Galilean realism have problems (see block
2)
2. Galileo was not just defining reality. They were making discoveries. Aristotelian physics, mechanics and astronomy were empirically inadequate. For example, claims that natural motion was circular (shared by Galileo), explanation of motion in terms of natural place in the universe, account of the motion of planets etc were empirically inadequate. Those failures were reasons for rejecting his ontology. Likewise the success of Newtonian mechanics are reasons for acceptance of a different scientific ontology.
3. Neither modern science nor an interest in technical control
are historically specific:
a. Galilean science itself developed within a long tradition: Greek atomism,
Archimedean mechanics and Neo-platonism were all influential
b. In interest in controlling and manipulating nature is part of the human
condition - we are not angels. (this is a problem that Habermas' develops)
4. Some analytical points about 'prediction', 'control'
'domination' and 'manipulation'.
Marcuse assumes that there is a necessary connection between measurement
and prediction and technical control, and between technical control and
domination. The assumptions are false.
a. Prediction does not entail control:
One can measure and predict that which one cannot control - witness the
history of astronomy on which the scientific revolution focused.
Moreover even if the power to predict does increase the power to control
it does not follow that an interest in prediction is based upon an interest
in control
b. Control does not entail domination.
'Control' and 'Manipulation' can be used in a minimal sense to refer to
'making things happen' without entailing the specific forms of control
involved in domination as involving the unacceptable use of power to control
autonomous beings.
Given that it makes sense to talk of dominating nature, one can control
without domination: to reduce greenhouse gases is to try to control nature,
but it is not to dominate it. Rather, it is to nurture it by attempting
to stop conditions that would decrease, for example, biodiversity.
To 'protect' and 'cultivate' the natural world itself requires certain
forms of intervention in the natural world.
* H. Blanke, ‘Domination and Utopia: Marcuse’s Discourse on Nature, Psyche, and Culture’, in Minding Nature: The Philosophers of Ecology, ed. D. Macauley (New York: Guilford Press, 1996). A very useful overview which brings out the influence of Marcuse’s earlier study of Freud and of the excessive repression exerted by capitalist societies.
* * W. Leiss, ‘Appendix’ to The Domination of Nature. Surveys debates about Marcuse’s idea of an alternative science.
W. Leiss, ‘Technological Rationality: Marcuse and his Critics’. In Philosophy of the Social Sciences 2 (1972), pp. 31-42.
J. O’Neill, ‘Marcuse, Husserl and the Crisis of the Sciences’. In Philosophy of Social Science 18 (1988), pp. 327-343.
J. O’Neill, Ecology, Policy and Politics (London: Routledge, 1993), ch. 9. A critical and usefully analytical account of Marcuse’s argument that scientific rationality embodies the ‘domination’ of nature.
S. Vogel, ‘New Science, New Nature: The Habermas-Marcuse Debate Revisited’, in Technology and the Politics of Knowledge, as cited above for the article by Pippin. Vogel traces Marcuse’s and Habermas’ views back to a tension within the Marxist tradition on whether science is essentially neutral or an aspect of the ideology of capitalist societies.
The recommended reading from Habermas is his article ‘Science and Technology as Ideology’ [1968], in Sociology of Science, ed. B. Barnes (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1972) pp. 74-85 |
Jürgen Habermas (1927- )
A social theorist and philosopher, Habermas is responsible for a renewal of critical theory. Influenced by Hegel, Marx and the earlier members of the Frankfurt School he extends and moderates their critique of logical positivism by incorporating aspsects of analytic philosophy: J.L. Austin, Searle and the later Wittgenstein.
His most influential work is the two volume Theory of Communicative Action (1981)
In response to Marcuse, Habermas accepts:
M1 (Modern natural science is necessarily committed to a view of nature
as an object to be manipulated and controlled);
M2 (A science of humans based on the model of the natural sciences is
thereby committed to the same view of humans);
and with qualifications M3 (Thus there is a necessary relations between
the scientific domination of nature and the scientific domination of humans).
Habermas rejects:
M4 (Modern natural science is historically specific and not the only form
that science can take); and
M5 (The liberation of both humans and nature requires a new science and
technology grounded in a different interest).
He offers various arguments for his rejection of M4 and
M5.
a. The interest in the instrumental manipulation of nature is not historically
specific. Instrumental action on nature - work or labour - is part of
the human condition. We are not angels but beings that must manipulate
the natural world to satisfy our needs. Hence labour is universal.
b. Science is constituted by an interest in successful instrumental action (accepts M1 - that the methods and concepts of science reveal an interest in technological manipulation of nature). However, since this interest in technical control is a universal interest, there is no reason to assume there could be another new science associated with another interests.
c. Marcuse's new science, which involves treating nature
as a subject in its own right, involves a confusion of instrumental action
and communicative action.
To treat nature as a subject involves acting towards natural objects as
one does towards people, as persons with whom communicative action is
possible. However, that kind of action is only appropriate towards persons
whose utterances and actions are open to interpretation. Nature is not
a possible partner in communicative action. It does not talk back.
Communicative action, like work, is a universal feature of human life,
but it cannot replace work and instrumental action.
d. Habermas assumes the following picture:
Instrumental action | work | natural science | nature |
Communicative action | language | hermeneutics (concerned with interpretation) | persons |
Marcuse, he thinks, conflates those two forms of action.
e. Habermas still accepts M1, M2 and M3
The problem in modern society is that instrumental action associated with
science is extended beyond its appropriate domain. Reduction of political
and ethical life to the application of instrumental reason for the realisation
of 'non-rational ends' - scientisation of society founded upon an ideology
of 'scientism' - that only science gives knowledge. This leads to a colonisation
of the life-world by instrumental reason.
Habermas' basic claim is that different forms of knowledge with different object domains and standards of validity are constituted by different interests that are founded in distinct forms of human activity. This is laid out in the table below:
Kinds of Knowledge | Empirical-Analytic:Natural Science | Historical-Hermeneutic: Interpretive | Critical Self-reflective |
Constitutive Interests | Technical Interest: prediction/control | Practical Interest: successful communication | Emancipatory Interest |
Object Domain | Things Events |
Persons Utterances Actions |
Distorted forms of action and utterance |
Criteria of Validity | Empirical testing | Agreement between partners in dialogue | Successful Emancipation |
Fundamental Activity of the Species | Work/labour: rational purposive action | Language/Symbolic-communicative action | ?? (In later work tied back to communication. Discourse ethics and ideal speech situation) |
The problem for Habermas is how to show that the
sciences are constituted by different interests. In particular: how is
science constituted by a technical interest? That is, in what sense does
a technical interest in the control of nature entail a particular object
domain and criteria of validity?
There is an accessible answer to this in B. Fay's Social Theory and
Political Practice.
Fay in outline:
The nature of explanation in natural science entails that there is a conceptual
link with an interest in technical control.
His argument appeals to deductive-nomological model of scientific explanation.
Explanation:
Laws: L1.....Ln
Initial conditions: C1.....Cm
Event to be explained: E
Implication of D-N model is that there is a structural identity of prediction
and explanation.
Hence scientific explanations provide just the sort of knowledge needed
to control events in the world.
Object of science = work of controllable objects and events.
Criteria of validity = given by success or failure of prediction.
A Possible Reply to Fay:
1. The claim that there is a necessary link between explanation and prediction
fails:
a. some explanations do not give predictions eg. Darwin's explanation
of the natural development of species;
b. some predictions are not explanations eg. Measles: Koplick spots always
followed by fever.
2. There is no necessary link between prediction and technical control.
There is an implicit realism in Habermas - He claims, and
must claim, that nature isn't a subject. But if objects are constituted
by an interest, how can we assert that nature isn't the sort of thing
that can be interpreted as a communicative actor?
The answer that 'natural objects don't talk back', entails a claim about
an object's independence of any 'constitution' claim.
Really useful web site is http://www.helsinki.fi/~amkauppi/hablinks.html
R. Bernstein (ed.), Habermas and Modernity (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1985): see sections I-III of the ‘Introduction’ (which deal generally with Habermas and the broader epistemological theory within which his account of science and technology belongs) and the paper by A. Wellmer, ‘Reason, Utopia, and the Dialectic of Enlightenment’.
T. Bottomore, The Frankfurt School (London: Methuen, 1984), offers an overall introduction to Habermas.
J. Thompson and D. Held (eds.), Habermas: Critical Debates (London: Macmillan, 1982). See especially the opaper by H. Ottman, ‘Cognitive Interests and Self-Reflection’, which again critically examines the epistemological background to Habermas’ view of science.
Bear in mind too that many of the readings on Marcuse consider Habermas, because they are assessing how effectively Habermas improves on Marcuse’s critique of technological rationality.