The rhetoric of deliberation
Please read chapter 10 'The Rhetoric of deliberation' available
on the discussion site.
A. Kant deliberation and rhetoric
1. Public use of reason
We noted in the last section that recent work on deliberative democracy
has Kantian roots. Deliberative institutions are taken to be embodiments
of the "public use of reason" that Kant takes to define the
enlightenment project: the "freedom to make public use of one's reason
in all matters" is a condition for the emergence of maturity - the
capacity and courage "to use one's own understanding without the
guidance of another" (Kant (1784) pp.54-55)
In developing this position the deliberative theorist calls upon the
distinction between reason and power. Thus Kant contrasts reason and "dictatorial
authority" : "For reason has no dictatorial authority; its verdict
is always simply the agreement of free citizens, of whom each one must
be permitted to express, without let or hindrance, his objections or even
his veto." (Kant (1933) A738/B766.) Similarly Habermas in drawing
the distinction between strategic and communicative actions distinguishes
between the force of institutional and personal power and the impersonal
force of argument, "the forceless force of the better argument".
The distinction that Habermas and Kant draw upon here is an ancient one
that goes back as far as Plato's criticisms of the sophists. Plato there
calls upon a contrast between rhetoric and reason. He distinguishes between
two forms of persuasion "one providing conviction without knowledge
(rhetoric), the other providing knowledge (dialectic)" (Plato Gorgias
454e). Rhetoric is concerned with producing conviction in its audience
without knowledge and without reason. Unlike specific sciences such as
mathematics it persuades not by teaching but by flattery. It issues not
in learning but mere conviction. It is not properly an art at all, but
a mere knack.
Plato's text is still the starting point for much subsequent discussion.
You can find it at:
http://www.ilt.columbia.edu/publications/Projects/digitexts/plato/gorgias/gorgias.html
This contrast between rhetoric and rational discourse is central to the
Kantian model of deliberative institutions which belongs to the long anti-rhetorical
tradition that can be traced back to Plato. Rhetoric is presented as an
art of deceit which, since it aims at persuasions without reason, is inconsistent
with respect for the autonomy of the hearer. Thus Kant himself while he
allows rhetoric a place in the arts which make no claim to be making assertions
of truth, it has no place in discourses that do make such claims:
'Poetry plays with illusion, which it produces at will, and yet without
using illusion to deceive us, for poetry tells us that its pursuit is
mere play...Oratory [on the other hand], insofar as this is taken to
mean the art of persuasion (ars oratoria), i.e. of deceiving by beautiful
illusion, rather than excellence of speech (eloquence and style), is
a dialectic that borrows from poetry only as much as the speaker needs
in order to win over people's minds for his own advantage before they
can judge for themselves, and so make their judgement unfree.'
2. Public choice/rhetorical response: reason as power
There is a standard sophist response to this tradition which is to be
found in both ancient and modern texts.
Ancient Sophism: The distinction between reasoned persuasion and other
forms of compulsion is denied. All deliberation is ultimately an art of
rhetoric understood as an art of manipulation.
A fine version of this view is to be found in Gorgias Praise
of Helen. Reading the fragment that remains, especially 8-15. This can
be found at: http://www.phil.vt.edu/MGifford/phil2115/Helen.htm
Question:
Gorgias claims of Helen that if she was persuaded by speech she did not
do wrong. Do you think this is right? Is there a contrast to be drawn
between the force of speech and the other forms of force that Gorgias
outlines? In particular is there a distinction to be drawn between rational
dialogue and manipulative or strategic uses of language?
Modern sophism:
Some versions of postmodern theory similarly deny there is a clear distinction
to drawn between rational deliberation and other forms of persuasion.
Strategic uses often typical of deliberative institutions in practice
should not be understood as mere mis-uses that fall short of the standards
of proper deliberation. They are all one could expect. They reveal the
ways in which truth and objectivity themselves are mere rhetorical ploys
that are designed to move an audience.
Against the new sophism
There is a performative contradiction at operation in the authors' utterances
in making these claims. If one took the claims seriously, one could not
take seriously their acts of saying them.
However while there may be problems with the strong sophist rejection
of the distinction between reason and rhetoric it does not follow that
there are not major problems in the Kantian view. The strong rhetorical
position needs to be kept distinct from weaker positions which allow the
legitimacy of rhetorical dimensions of public deliberation without holding
that all communication is strategic (Young's 1996, 2000 defence of rhetoric
can be read in this way). There may be dimensions of communication that
are a proper part of public deliberation, which are consistent with respect
for the autonomy of the hearer, but which Kantian models of deliberation
exclude.
Two features of public discourse highlighted by rhetorical analysis are
of particular importance in this regard: testimony and the role of emotions.
1. Reason and authority: 'the only remaining authority is that of a good
argument'.
There is very little we believe only on the authority of argument - most
of what we believe we do so no the basis of testimony. We rely upon credible
sources of knowledge and necessarily so.
In public policy this gives rise to problems of trust and credibility.
In context of scientific uncertainty and contested scientific claim the
citizen asks 'Who do I believe?' What sources of knowledge are trustworthy?
2. Role of appeal to emotions
Deliberation aims at decision. Hence it has to move individuals not just
instruct them.
Both of these, in the Kantian perspective, are potential sources of heteronomy.
- "Testimony requires us to attend to persons, not propositions.
However to believe something on the basis of the authoritativeness of
the person and not on the basis of reasons is to make oneself dependent
upon another.
- To be moved by emotions is likewise to be governed by something independent
of judgement. Moreover, that something is not ultimately the objects
of our passions but other persons" (Kant, 1974, 269-70).
Since rhetoric is concerned both with the self-presentation of the trustworthiness
of the speaker and with addressing the emotions of the hearer, it is incompatible
with respect for autonomy.
Questions:
Can these features of public deliberation be
eliminated from public deliberation?
Are they incompatible with reasoned discourse and autonomy?
A difference between Aristotle's account of rhetoric and public deliberations
is its denial of the Platonic contrast between reasoned discourse and
rhetoric which the Kantian model inherits. We will consider if the Aristotelian
account is more defensible.
B. Aristotle and rhetoric
Read Aristotle Rhetoric book One, chapters 1 and
2 available at
http://eserver.org/philosophy/aristotle/rhetoric.txt
It is from Aristotle that we have the standard definition of rhetoric.
Rhetoric is the art of persuasion: "the faculty of observing in any
given case the available means of persuasion" (Aristotle 1946 Book
I.2). But Aristotle also rejects the account of rhetoric as persuasion
without reason. Hence he begins the Rhetoric with criticism of
previous models of rhetoric for ignoring the place of argument in the
art (Aristotle 1946 Book I.1). Rhetoric is not set in opposition to rational
argument: rather rhetoric presupposes it. Rhetoric deals in those forms
of persuasion that essentially employ language. Aristotle outlines three
modes of persuading through words:
1. providing arguments themselves that are persuasive;
2. exhibiting the authoritative and virtuous character of the speaker;
3. moving the emotions of the audience.
1. Persuasive argument:
Dialectical and logical argument. Aristotle distinguishes logical and
dialectical argument thus:
a. Logic deals in demonstrative inferences from premises that 'true and
primary' that is, 'believed not on the strength of anything else but themselves'
such that 'it is improper to ask any further why and wherefore of them'.
b. Dialectical argument
- Employs persuasive arguments, or to use Burnyeat's apt phrase 'relaxed
arguments', that is arguments that are not deductively valid, but make
justifiable claims on the rational mind.
- Reasons from endoxa, authoritative opinions: 'it reasons from opinions
that are generally accepted....which are accepted by everyone or by
the majority or by the philosophers - i.e. by all, or by the majority,
or by the most notable and illustrious of them...'. Such opinions form
the starting point for inquiry: we need to begin from 'what is known
to us', not from propositions known 'unconditionally' that form the
starting point for logical inquiry.
2. The presentation of character.
But since rhetoric exists to affect the giving of decisions - the hearers
decides between one political speaker and another, and a legal verdict
is a decision - the orator must not only try to make the argument of his
speech demonstrative and worthy of belief; he must also make his own character
look right and put his hearers, who are to decide, in the right frame
of mind.
3. The appeal to emotions
The emotions themselves answer to reason and are open to rational persuasion.
This point is a central part to what distinguishes Aristotelian defence
of rhetoric from the anti-rhetorical tradition in philosophy.
C. Testimony rhetoric and character
Environment, trust and testimony
Issues of trust and credibility are central to a large number of problems
in public policy which involve scientific expertise and are subject to
controversy. The citizen has to make judgements about whose testimony
is trustworthy, who is credible. This is a problem that the various ‘new’
deliberative institutions such as citizens’ juries and citizens’
panels often address. The problem of a decline in trust in ‘scientific
expertise’ forms the starting point of many practical applications
of deliberative institutions, particularly those applied to risk. It is
in part for that reason that environmental spheres have been such a prominent
site for experiments in deliberative democracy.
The Aristotelian model of public deliberation appears to deal better
than the Kantian account with issues of testimony and trust.
Credibility:
For Aristotle credibility has two dimensions
epistemological - the speaker must have good sense and
be reliable in the formation of judgements
ethical - the speaker must have the moral character that allows us to
trust their utterance and there must be grounds for believing that they
are not inclined to impart falsehoods to their audience
False statements and bad advice are due to one or more of the following
three causes. Men either from a false opinion through want of good sense;
or they form a true opinion, but because of their moral badness do not
say what they really think; or finally, they are both sensible and upright,
but not be well disposed to their hearers...
In contrast to the Kantian position, for Aristotle, evaluation of the
character of sources of belief is central to our most basic knowledge
claims.
Credibility, institutions and politics
In the modern world the issue of credible testimony has an institutional
and political focus: testimony is offered to us by strangers, by 'spokespersons'
and 'experts', who call upon us to believe what they say on the basis
of certification from institutions - academic, industrial, commercial
and political.
What institutions deserve epistemological trust in what conditions?
Any answer requires a political epistemology concerning conditions of
trust, and a corresponding social and political theory about its institutional
preconditions.
The association of evaluative practices with positions of social power
and wealth for example induces quite proper scepticism about its reliability.
Credibility and the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK)
Much that goes by the name of anti-realism and relativism in SSK is in
fact aimed at a form of intellectualism, that makes the credibility of
a claim purely a matter of how well it is supported by other propositions.
Shapin:SSK rejects the view that:
The credibility and the validity [sic.] of a proposition ought to
be one and the same. Truth shines by its own lights...Once upon a time...students
of sciences...believed that truth was its own recommendation, or if
not that, something very like it. If one wanted to know, and one rarely
did, why it was that true propositions were credible, one was referred
back to their truth, to the evidence for them, or to those methodical
procedures the unambiguous following of which testified to the truth
of the product.
If the issue is one of credibility of knowledge-claims and not their
truth, then it is quite proper to point to the variety of social causes
of credibility.
It does not follow that truth or knowledge are thereby social constructions
unless one already accepts a naive cognitivist identification of credibility
and truth.
Neither does it follow that credibility is a sufficient condition of knowledge
or that it is a necessary condition - that 'no credibility, no knowledge'.
D. Autonomy, maturity and emotion
Classical distinction between rhetoric and dialectic
- Dialectic has theoretical aims - truth
- Rhetoric has practical aims - to move an audience to action.
The difference maps onto the traditional distinctions between being instructed
and being moved.
Question:
Does an appeal to the emotions render deliberation irrational?
Consider that question before continuing.
The anti-rhetorical tradition: the appeal to emotion renders rhetoric
irrational.
Kant on the emotions:
Emotions are feelings, capacities for psychological sensations of pleasure
or pain that might sometimes accompany cognitive states but they are
themselves without any cognitive dimension. (Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue:
Part II of The Metaphysic of Morals, 210-11)
Since the passions are non-cognitive it follows that reasoned discourse
cannot appeal to the emotions.
Hence it follows that appeals to the emotion move us without engaging
our judgements.
As such they render the agent passive, someone who is impelled to act
without rational deliberation and choice. Hence, to move an agent by appeal
to emotions is to render them unfree. Thus rhetoric is rejected as inconsistent
with reason and autonomy.
Aristotle and the rationality of the emotions
The emotions themselves answer to reason and are open to rational persuasion.
This point is central part to what distinguishes Aristotelian defence
of rhetoric from the anti-rhetorical tradition in philosophy.
The emotions are open to the appraisal of reason:
We can be afraid, e.g., or be confident, or have appetite, or get
angry, or feel pity, in general have pleasure or pain, both too much
and too little, and in both ways not well; but [having these feelings]
at the right times, about the right things, towards the right people,
for the right end, and in the right way, is the intermediate and best
condition, and this is proper to virtue.
Because emotions have this dimension they are open to appraisal. They
can be appropriate or inappropriate, felt at the right time, of the right
things, for the right reasons or not.
I feel anger because a distant relative forgets my birthday - the emotion
is irrational, since I know that no slight is intended. I feel anger at
the dismissal of a colleague: the anger is quite rational for the harm
is intentional and unjustified.
It follows that the emotions are not deaf to reason, but open to the
rational persuasion (Aristotle 1985 Book I ch.13). Emotions are constituted
by beliefs and can be roused by addressing these. I rouse your anger by
pointing to unjustified harm the logging company does. I placate your
anger at a farmer who destroys a valuable habitat by placing her action
in the context of grinding poverty: your anger is redirected to those
responsible for this, and in its place you are moved to pity the farmer
and her family. Such appeals are the stuff of everyday discourse and public
debate.
Emotions and political deliberation
Aristotle:
- the role of the emotions in motivating action is not simply a case
of it supplying a non-rational drive or impulse to movement.
- to educate the emotions is to develop cognitive capacities of perception
and judgement, not simply behavioural tendencies to movement.
Sceptical remarks
Is there something as heroic and unrealistic about the Aristotelian
version of maturity as there is about the Kantian?
- The picture of a perfect harmony between practical wisdom and emotional
response is implausible of empirical agents.
- As Kant notes, there is also a passivity about emotions. On occasions
we are overwhelmed by emotion, and moved to act in ways in which are
against our better judgements.
The Stoic
Emotions are not the kind of states that are always open to moderation.
Emotions run away with us and move us to excess. Hence the disastrous
role the appeal to emotions like can anger have in public life (Seneca
‘On Anger’ J. Cooper and J. Procope eds. Seneca: Moral and
Political Essays)
The Problem
Against the Stoic: Neither the Stoic view of the emotions - that they
are false judgements - nor the Stoic cure to such dangers - the elimination
of the emotions - are plausible.
They fall together. The emotions do not always involve false judgements
about what is of value - pity or anger felt appropriately involve true
judgement and perception. Emotions are not eliminable just because they
are capacities for proper judgement and concern about what matters in
private and public life.
The response to the dangers of rhetorical appeals to the emotions that
impel us to false judgement is not to imagine that good deliberation could
do without appeal to emotions. Rather it is to design institutions to
minimise the dangers that follow.
|