Away MAVEThe Distance Mode of MA in Values and the Environment at Lancaster University Block 4: Deep Ecology and Ecofeminism |
|||||||||||
|Home|Aims and Outcomes|Module Description|Tutor Details|Biblio|Assessment|Resources| Discussion
NB These materials do not represent the current (05/06) version of this module, and are offered here as only as an additional resource for students of environmental ethics.In this block, we are going to explore two schools of thought
in environmental philosophy - deep ecology and ecofeminism - that, to
some extent at least, suggest that the approaches to environmental ethics
we have considered so far in this module are wrongheaded. As will soon
become clear, it's important to note that neither deep ecology nor ecofeminism
are easy to define. Both deep ecology and ecofeminism are clusters of
ideas, not all of which are held by those who might call themselves 'deep
ecologists' or ecofeminists and some held by those who definitely would
not. In both cases, different concepts are prioritised differently by
different thinkers, and there are a number of different streams of thought
under both headings! Deep EcologyBeginnings The expression Deep Ecology is usually traced back to a
paper published in 1973 by the Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess. Born
in Norway in 1912, Naess already had pursued a long and highly respected
philosophical career as a philosopher (as well as a mountaineer), and
was the founder of the philosophical journal Inquiry. His article "The
Shallow and the Deep, LongRange Ecology Movement" published in this
journal (Inquiry 16 1973) is regarded as the founding document
of the deep ecology movement. This very brief summary makes clear three different 'faces' of the deep ecology movement. First, it advocates a change in the way humans view the world - which we might call a metaphysical face. Secondly, it advocates a change in ethics; and thirdly, it suggests various political changes. That is to say, deep ecology has a metaphysical, an ethical and a political face. Indeed, it suggests that Western cultures need a 'paradigm shift' in order to construct a world changed in all these three aspects. And it is, broadly speaking, in accord with these three faces that deep ecology has expanded and diversified from Naess' original article. Deep ecology has been viewed as a metaphysical or consciousness movement, concerned with changing the way the world is interpreted; as an ethical approach, concerned with the value of organisms and species; and as a political movement, concerned with local autonomy, democracy, and bioregionalism (being self sufficient within one's biological region). It's a mistake to split these aspects off too much, since the metaphysical shifts are sometimes seen as a basis for the other aspects, and there are ways in which all can be quite closely related. But thinking about these three 'faces' does help to clarify some basic ideas in deep ecology, so I'm just going to briefly look at them, and some of their main developments, more closely. Deep Ecology and Metaphysics/ConsciousnessNaess' statement that deep ecology was in part about 'rejection of the man-in-environment image in favour of the relational, total field image' has been the trigger for wide-ranging material in deep ecology. At root here is the view that it is relationships and interconnections which are fundamental in the world, rather than the world as being a collection of separate things. Influencing this view of the world have been ideas derived from the 'new physics' which emphasise that the world was a field of energy. One person whose work is sometimes drawn on here is the physicist Frizjof Capra, who wrote the well known popular physics books The Turning Point and The Tao of Physics. Capra argues that traditional views of the world based around mechanism (everything that exists has a mechanical explanation) and reductionism (the best way to understand something is by breaking it down into its component parts) are based on a view of physics which has been superseded. They work with an atomistic understanding of the world - where the world is built out of solid particles. But the new physics, primarily quantum physics and relativity, Capra argues, present a very different view of the world. Here, the world is seen as an interconnected web of relations; subatomic particles cannot be understood as isolated entities.
Supporting material is also drawn from ecology and the emphasis on ecosystems and the degree of interdependence between them. The ecological writer Barry Commoner is sometimes cited here - because he described the principle that everything is interconnected as the 'First Law of Ecology'. Metaphysical developments of deep ecology, then, have generally adopted views of this kind. We can identify a number of key points as follows:
Must metaphysical claims about the world at least be
compatible with scientific thinking, even if they don't claim support
from it?
|
BASIC PRINCIPLES OF DEEP ECOLOGY Proposed by Naess and Sessions 1984, From Sessions
and Devall Deep Ecology (Utah, Peregrine 1985) |
Thinking
about the Basic Principles - some questions
have a go at each of these in your own notes
1) The principles claim as valuable all living organisms
and also 'richness and diversity'.
Plainly these are different kinds of things. What might one do when they
clash?
2) Do you think deep ecologists would always want to affirm diversity as a value? Doesn't it suggest, for instance, that there's an obligation to genetically engineer lots of new, different organisms?
3) What might 'richness' of life forms be, if not diversity?
4) And the question everyone always raises - what are vital needs? Naess, discussing this point in the second reading below, says that it's "deliberately left vague". Is this helpful - or unhelpful?
5) The principles clearly suggest the need for human population decrease - and the last point suggests that if you agree you should try to implement the changes. What should one do to reduce population? Is not having your own children an appropriate response?
6) The principles talk about human 'interference' in the non-human world. Here's that problem again, that we came upon in block 3. If humans are to be separated from the non-human world - such that they can 'interfere' with it, how can they also be one with it? This seems to contradict the holistic metaphysics emphasised earlier. Deep ecologists want both to say that humans are natural, and that they should reduce interference with nature. Is there a way around this?
7) What does an obligation to attempt to implement the principles mean? (we shall be looking at this briefly in the next section).
The third way in which deep ecology has developed is as a political movement - using the term political in a very broad sense. Some of the places where deep ecology has been of political importance are:
In summary, bioregionalism, as suggested above, is
about regional self-sufficiency. Advocates of bioregionalism divide the
earth into a series of 'bioregions' - areas which constitute one integrated
ecosystem - such as watersheds. These bioregions, it is argued, should
form the point of identity for populations rather than the artificial
boundaries of states and counties. Individuals should be educated about
the ecology of their bioregion. Bioregions should aim at being increasingly
self-sufficient in food and other materials and reducing their imports
from other bioregions. It's also often argued that bioregions should be
units of government too - thus the political boundaries would reflect
natural boundaries. In summary, it's argued, the development of bioregions
would help people to identify with and feel part of their environment,
and would also reduce the massive transportation costs of a global market
in goods and services.
Reading tip: The most well-known writer on bioregionalism is Kirkpatrick Sale. If you want to pursue this further, read Kirkpatrick Sale (1985) Dwellers in the Land: The Bioregional Vision (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books). |
We are going to look at wilderness in more detail in Block 5. But for now it is useful to note that Deep Ecologists, especially in the United States, have been closely associated with wilderness protection movements. (This is obviously in line with the 8 principles). This has included radical environmental activism - the 'organisation' Earth First!, well known for its tactics of protest, sit-ins, sabotage of environmentally-damaging equipment like bulldozers, spiking trees etc grew out of the deep ecology movement and adopted a programme of direct action. Many environmental actions in Europe and the US have been undertaken by those adhering to some form of deep ecology. Generally speaking, these activists are non-violent, against people at least.
This is a third area in which deep ecologists have been involved (and here I'm stretching the word 'political' to its limits). Spirituality has been important to some many deep ecologists right from the start (hence some scathing dismissal of deep ecology as eco-la-la from environmentalists less inclined to adopt a spiritual approach!) As we shall see when we come to the readings, spirituality is certainly not alien to Naess' writing. Spiritual developments of deep ecology have been myriad (within paganism, Buddhism and Christianity, amongst others). Sometimes they have involved adopting practices associated with indigenous peoples (such as the use of sweat lodges in the US, an American Indian practice.) Another spiritual practice adopted by some deep ecologists has been what is called 'A Council of All Beings'. In this ritual, each participant adopts the identity of a particular creature, speaks for it and plays its role: a practice which attempts to encourage participants to identify with members of other species.
Reading Tip: There have been a number of attacks on deep ecology from a range of other positions. However, one of the most interesting and wide-ranging philosophical critiques was by the late Richard Routley/Sylvan (the author of the first reading in Block 1 and a formidable environmental philosopher in his own right). The article is quite long, but it's well worth reading. See Sylvan, Richard (1985) "A Critique of Deep Ecology" Radical Philosophy 40 & 41 |
Reading on Deep Ecology: "The Deep Ecological Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects" - in Zimmermann pp 193-211 This reading tells us quite a lot about Naess, his philosophical background, and his understanding of deep ecology. |
Exercise
To be clear that you've grasped some of the central
ideas he's talking about, try to summarise to yourself
1) How he understands the 'deep' in deep ecology
2) What he means by 'ecosophy' in general
3) How he understands Ecosophy T in particular
4) What he means by 'Self-realisation!' of both humans and non-human
5) What he means by 'total view'
1) Naess suggests that deep ecology can have a variety
of different backgrounds or contexts (eg Buddhism, Christianity etc) but
that deep ecologists should converge on the 8-point platform (the apron
diagram illustrates this). Does this mean that Naess' deep ecology is
pluralist, and if so, in what sense? What do you make of the apron diagram?
2) Do you think that Naess' vision of a much simpler society is utterly
unrealistic? Might it have economic consequences he doesn't take into
account?
3) In his discussion of the 8-point platform Naess suggests that rivers,
landscapes and ecosystems count as "living". Do they? In what
sense?
4) Can there be a "core democracy in the biosphere"?
5) Naess maintains that we naturally delight in diversity. Do we? How
could we know this? Does this mean that ethnocentrism (for instance) is
stunting our natural love for diversity?
6) Must deep ecology be religious (in some sense of the word?)
7) Is it indecent for a teacher to proclaim an ethic for tactical reasons
only? (p.196)
8) What similarities, and what key differences do you see between deep
ecology and positions in environmental ethics we've already looked at
- in particular that of Paul Taylor, and the land ethic?
Send your response to question 8 to the
discussion site
Reading 2 Harold Glasser 'Demystifying the Critiques of Deep Ecology' in Zimmermann pp 212-226 |
1. Glasser argues that 'deep ecology' is frequently
misunderstood, albeit in a variety of different ways. Do you think that
he is right about this? How significant are these 'misunderstandings'?
2. On p.218, Glasser discusses Naess' 'anti-dogmatism'. Do you think Naess
is anti-dogmatic?
3. Is Naess right to suggest, as Glasser reports (p 219) that humans 'act
as if we have systematic conceptual structures for relating to the world,
total views'?
4. Does Glasser's discussion of The Deep Ecology Platform (DEP) cast any
further light on its role in the deep ecology movement?
Useful websites on deep ecology:Interview with Michael Zimmermann
http://www.erraticimpact.com/~ecologic/html/deep_ecology.htm#onlineArticle by Stephen Harding in Resurgence on Deep Ecology
http://www.gn.apc.org/resurgence/185/harding185.htm
Having looked at deep ecology, and its contribution
to debates in environmental ethics, I now want to move on to ecofeminism,
and to think about how the variety of views encompassed by this term also
contribute to thinking about the environment ethically. Ecofeminists,
especially Plumwood, have also offered a range of further objections to
deep ecology, which we can look at in the next section in more detail.
The term 'ecofeminism' was first used in 1974 by
Francoise D'Eaubonne. Since then ecofeminism has become a large but diverse
movement, encompassing thinkers from a wide range of perspectives from
within the feminist movement and the environmental movement. Although
ecofeminism is diverse, there does seem to be one core shared premise:
that there is a link between what is understood as the domination of nature
and the domination of women. Sometimes this is expressed as the view that
oppression of women and the natural world are 'twin' oppressions, stemming
from the same cause. Here's a classic statement of this perceived link:
"Women must see that there can be no liberation for them and no solution
to the ecological crisis within a society whose fundamental model of relationship
is domination. They must unite the demands of the women's movement with
those of the ecological movement to envisage a radical reshaping of the
basic socio-economic relations and the underlying values of this society"
Ruether, Rosemary Radford (1975) New Woman/New Earth p.204
The language of oppression and domination makes clear that this is a value-movement: ecofeminists argue that both the oppression of women and nature is wrong, and should be eliminated. However, the nature of the link between these twin oppressions has been understood in many different ways and consequently the best way of eliminating these twin oppressions is also contested.
Some have wanted to question this fundamental premise of ecofeminism, by asking the following:
a)Can "oppression" mean the same thing when it's applied to women and when it's applied to nature?
b)What kind of evidence, and what volume of evidence could possibly be adduced to support the idea of a link between the oppression of women and nature?
To help in thinking about this question, read Karen Warren's introduction to the section on ecofeminism in Zimmermann: she provides a useful overview of all the different kinds of connections that have been claimed. |
Beyond this shared premise about the twin domination of women and nature,
there are a variety of different kinds of ecofeminism - as there are,
more broadly, a variety of kinds of feminism. Two of the most important
ecofeminisms are cultural ecofeminism and socialist ecofeminism. In brief,
cultural ecofeminists tend to argue that women are essentially different
from men, that they have a "nature"; in which particular characteristics
(such as nurturing) are manifested, and that this nature makes women close
to nature. (Note the use of "nature" in that sentence to mean
two different things - in the first instance it means inner essence; and
in the second, the non-human world). Sometimes cultural ecofeminism is
associated with a goddess-based spirituality; but however this is viewed,
in all cases, cultural ecofeminists argue that there should be a revaluation
of "women's work" including the bearing and bringing up of children.
Socialist ecofeminism on the other hand maintains that although it may
be widely thought that women are "closer to nature", this is
a social construction. Some women do not have such characteristics, some
men do, and everyone could learn them: that is to say, socialist ecofeminism
rejects these kinds of essentialist claims about human beings. For socialist
ecofeminists, racism, sexism, classism and naturism are entwined oppressions
which can be changed; and they are committed to achieving such changes.
Reading Tip : Carolyn Merchant's book Radical Ecology
(London: Routledge 1992) has a chapter introducing and outlining different
kinds of ecofeminism. Like deep ecology, ecofeminism has been worked out in a variety of spheres, including social theory and politics, and these aspects are important in getting a broader picture of ecofeminism as a movement. But since there is a good deal to say relating to environmental ethics, we will spend the rest of this block thinking about ecofeminism in an ethical context. |
Ecofeminists have offered a wide range of criticisms of the mainstream approaches to environmental ethics we considered in blocks 2 and 3, and also of deep ecology. Iwant to start by looking at some of these criticisms, because they provide a useful point of access from which to think about ecofeminist ethics in general. Three of these criticisms are summarized below.
Ecofeminists point out that many of the main approaches to environmental ethics we've considered emphasise rationality and denigrate feeling. Such a view, of course, characterizes many ethical positions, not just in environmental ethics. Kant, as you may remember, maintained that if one carried out an action in response to one's feelings, then it couldn't be ethical. Similar positions are maintained by a variety of environmental ethicists - see below:
"We were not especially "interested in" animals. Neither of us had ever been inordinately fond of dogs, cats or horses in the way that many people are. We didn't "love" animals. ..The assumption that in order to be interested in such matters one must be an "animal-lover" is itself an inclination of the absence of the slightest inkling that the moral standards we apply amongst human beings might extend to other animals….The portrayal of those who protest against cruelty to animals as sentimental, emotional animal lovers has had the effect of excluding the entire issue of our treatment of nonhumans from serious political and moral discussion" Singer (1975) Preface to Animal Liberation p. ix
"The attitude of respect for persons …is both a moral one and an ultimate one. It is a moral attitude because it is universalizable and disinterested. That is, each moral agent who sincerely has the attitude advocates its universal adoption by all other agents, regardless of whether they are so inclined and regardless of their fondness or lack of fondness for other individuals" Taylor (1986) Respect for Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press) p. 41
Ecofeminists, on the other hand, want to emphasise the importance of feeling in our ethical behaviour. Humans are not purely rational beings- we are not Dr Spocks! Ethics, they argue, should take into account that we are more complex beings composed from emotions as well as reason - and, further, that reason and emotion cannot be separated as easily as such approaches to ethics might suggest.
Ecofeminists point out that mainstream approaches to environmental ethics work on abstract principles of justice that are supposed to apply to all people everywhere. Underlying this is the traditional view that ethics must be universalisable. This "universalisation" plainly has different forms in different approaches to ethics. It might mean, as in Kant, a universal law. It might mean putting yourself in the position of an ideal observer. It might mean making the same calculations everyone would make. But in all these instances, the idea that a moral judgement should be universalisable, appropriate for everyone in that situation, and thus impersonal is fundamental. Singer, again, makes a classic statement of such a position:
"My ability to reason shows me the possibility of detaching myself from my own perspective and shows me what the universe might look like if I had no personal perspective". (Singer: How are we to Live p.229)
For some ecofeminist ethicists, this kind of position ignores the complex and particular nature of ethical situations in which we might find ourselves. It might be that in the same situation it is appropriate for different people to do different things, given their history, their background and their relations to other people involved. Nel Noddings, a leading feminist ethicist, puts it like this:
"A and B, struggling with a moral decision, are two different persons with different factual histories, different projects and aspirations and different ideals. It may indeed be right, morally right, for A to do X and B to do not-X." Noddings, Nel (1982) Caring (California University Press) p.85-6
Furthermore, ecofeminists urge that we should be suspicious of claims to be working from a universal position, the impartial "point of view" of the universe. Might not such "impartiality" simply obscure the interests of those involved by cloaking them in impartial language? In a sense this echoes a kind of Nietzschean understanding of ethics: that ethical positions are driven by underlying emotional commitments, but that in a step of self-deception these underlying commitments are not acknowledged, and claim to be "rationality". Look for instance at how Regan thinks "conformity with reflective intuitions" is important in ethics. But where have these intuitions come from? What drives them?
A further problem ecofeminists raise with many approaches
to environmental ethics is the search for necessary and sufficient "qualities"
to earn moral considerability. If you have the right quality: sentience,
subject-of-a-life, being alive etc - you can be let into the magic circle;
if not, you are left outside it. Animal liberation theorists are obviously
the greatest offenders in this respect - since they, especially Regan
- leave most of the environment outside of the circle of moral considerability.
But ecofeminists tend to argue that ethics should not be about expanding
the circle in this sense - looking for ever broader and more inclusive
criteria - but changing the terms on which things come to matter. Rather
than search for essences - which is intrinsically individual-focused-
they suggest, we should turn to relationships. This has the advantage
of allowing for much more particular and contextual thinking. It allows
non-humans to be taken into account individually, and differences between
them to be considered. For instance, for Singer there is no moral difference
between a pet dog and a wild wolf. Both are sentient and entitled to exactly
the same moral treatment. But ecofeminists want to ask much more detailed
questions about the individual animals, our relationships with them, how
they relate to human society and other members of their species, and so
on, before making moral decisions about how they should be treated.
reading tip Plumwood, Val "Nature, Self and Gender: Feminism, Environmental Philosophy and the Critique of Rationalism" in 1st and 2nd edition of Zimmermann. and Plumwood's 1993 book Feminism and the Mastery of Nature (London: Routledge). It's widely regarded as one of the best systematic accounts of ecofeminism. |
Ecofeminist ethicists have tended to reject this abstract, rational and universalist approach to ethical thinking suggesting instead that environmental ethics, rather than being based on a particular universalising understanding of reason, can instead be built on relationships of care between humans and the non-humans/particular environments in which they are located. This does not mean that reason should be abandoned altogether; but rather that as Plumwood argues in Feminism and the Mastery of Nature, reason should "find a form which encourages sensitivity to the conditions under which we exist on the earth…and enables us to acknowledge our debt to the sustaining others of the earth".
This idea of "care" has been central to the development of feminist ethics more generally. It stems from a ground-breaking work by Carol Gilligan, called In a Different Voice, published in 1982. Gilligan studied children at play in school grounds and noticed that boys and girls tended to have different ways of formulating play. Boys' games seemed to focus around abstract rules of justice, to which players had to conform, whereas girls' games seemed to concern relationships and the expression (or not) of care. From these observations, Glligan theorized that there were different ethical "voices" - the voice of justice and the voice of care - and that men were more often associated with the first voice, whilst women were associated with the second. (These associations were not exclusive - some girls and women did use a justice voice, or even alternated voices; and Glligan didn't suggest that these different voices were "natural" rather than socially constructed). Gilligan suggested that both voices had a place to play in ethics, and that the voice of care shouldn't be excluded, a point she makes very tellingly in the quotation below:
"Theoretically, the distinction between justice and care cuts across the familiar divisions between thinking and feeling, egoism and altruism, theoretical and practical reasoning. It call attention to the fact that all relationships, public and private can be characterised in terms both of equality and in terms of attachment. And that both inequality and detachment constitute grounds for moral concern. Since everyone is vulnerable both to oppression and abandonment, two moral visions - one of justice and one of care - recur in human experience". Gilligan, Carol (1994) "Moral Orientation and Moral Development" in May and Sharratt (eds) Applied Ethics (NJ: Prentice Hall) p.262
Reading Tip For a widely used, but controversial account of caring, see Noddings, Nel (1982) Caring (California University Press) Chapter 8 of this book is on "caring for plants, animals and other things" and suggests a view that we can't properly care for non-humans because they cannot recognise caring or reciprocate, and the nature of this non-response will not change (as with a human baby, for instance). |
The idea of a voice of care in ethics, has been taken
up by many ecofeminists as well as feminists more generally. It informs
some of the key elements which recur in ecofeminist ethics, such as:
· Relationship is fundamental in ethical decision-making;
· Ethics is contextual and particular, depending on the constellations of relationships involved in any particular set of circumstances;
· There's a need to develop ethical attitudes (we might even say virtues) such as empathy & affection;
· Ethical thinking should be based on attachment, not detachment. Rather than being seen as a moral virtue, detachment can be seen as a moral problem because it leads to moral blindness or indifference and a failure to discern need. "Detachment is considered the hallmark of mature moral thinking within a justice perspective, signifying the ability to judge dispassionately, to weigh evidence in an even-handed manner, balancing the claims of other and self. From a care perspective, detachment is the moral problem". (Gilligan, in May and Sharratt above, p. 271)
In order to see how this works out in a bit more detail, let's look at the fourth reading in this block, by one of the leading ecofeminist ethicists, Karen Warren.
Reading 4 Karen Warren 'The Power and Promise of Ecological Feminism' in Zimmermann pp 325-344. This article is often used as an introduction to ideas about ecofeminism. Warren identifies some of the ideas which she considers central to ecofeminism in general and evcofeminist ethics in particular. |
1) What does Warren mean by "oppressive conceptual
frameworks"?
2) What's a "logic of domination", and why is it so important
in Warren's analysis?
3) Do you think there's a kind of virtue theory lurking in Warren's argument
(eg on p. 333)?
4) How exactly does Warren interpret relationship? Look especially at
the top of p. 334.
1) Warren talks quite a bit about hierarchy, and when value hierarchical thinking is appropriate. Be sure you understand the distinctions she is making, and then think about some of the environmental ethicists we've considered (eg Regan or Attfield). Are they value-hierarchical? If so, would it be justifiably so in Warren's terms?
2) Can rocks be subordinated? Can one have relationships with them? Can one care for them? Does it matter whether one climbs a rock to dominate it, or as part of a caring relationship with it? If so, why?
3) Do you agree with Warren that rocks can have some kind of ethical significance, in contexts in which one is relating to them? Could it be argued that this is another extended kind of egocentrism?
4) On p. 328, Warren formally lays out a kind of argument she thinks has been historically pursued which has led to the oppression of both women and nature. Can you think of historical evidence for this argument? And do you think this argument can be found active today?
5) Warren seems to be arguing that feminism must be ecofeminism. Do you think she's right?
6) Is the "first person narrative" a possible way forward for
environmental ethics? If so, why? If not, why not?
7) How do you respond to the 8 principles of ecofeminist ethics Warren outlines? Are there points where you strongly agree or disagree? (There seems something odd in the text here - is there a repetition of the same points in slightly different words?)
1) If ecofeminist environmental ethics is contextual and non-universalist, does this mean that there are no absolutes, that "anything goes"? Warren, in the article we've looked at, resists this interpretation by suggesting a series of "boundary conditions" which must be met if an ethic is to be described as "feminist" at all (for instance, it must exclude sexism and racism). But can ecofeminists consistently have such boundary conditions? Does this compromise their contextualism?
2) Doesn't an ethic of care result in a kind of ethical nepotism? We've encountered this question earlier, but it is precisely to avoid this charge that the "mainstream" environmental ethicists practice universalisation! What kind of place can justice have in ecofeminist ethics?
3) What about people who don't care/can't care? Should they be re-educated? What if this doesn't work?
4) What about abusive relationships of care? What happens in cases where someone sacrifices themselves in caring to someone who abuses their care? Aren't there times when it is appropriate to stop caring (and perhaps think about self-justice?)
Web Tips:
The main ecofeminist site is at: http://www.ecofem.org/
For a bibliography, see http://www.ecofem.org/biblio/
There are a number of articles on ecofeminism in Ethics and the Environment Volume 4, Issue 2,
Pages 125-250 (1999) - a journal available online through the university library.
This block looked at deep ecology and ecofeminism
as important schools of thought in environmental philosophy. It considered
1. The diversity of both deep ecology and ecofeminism as schools of thought
2. Deep ecology as a movement with metaphysical, ethical and political
faces
3. The metaphysics of deep ecology with its emphasis on interrelatedness
and holism and versions of "the new physics" and ecology
4. The variant ethics of deep ecology including a form of biocentric egalitarianism,
but also positions valuing the "extended self"
5. The 8-point deep ecology platform
6. The political developments linked to deep ecology, including bioregionalism,
direct action and spiritual/ecological ritual
7. The writing of Arne Naess
8. Ecofeminism as emphasizing the "twin oppression" of women
and nature
9. The critique of "mainstream" environmental ethics by ecofeminists
on the grounds of its emphasis on rationality, universalisation, essentialism
10. Ecofeminist ethics emphasizing care, context, relationship and attachment
11. Karen Warren's account of ecofeminism.
To complete this block make sure that you have responded to some of your peer's contributions to the discussion site