Introduction
The most potent image of technology is of human mastery over nature.
The aim of technical innovation is to improve upon nature and better human
capacities. However, the dominance of this philosophy of mastery obscures
the existence of parallel philosophies of technological mimicry. Rather
than master nature, such technologies seek to model and imitate complex
natural systems. Mimetic notions of technology have become particularly
important in biomimetic nanotechnology and complexity theory. As a different
model of technical innovation such technologies offer a set of alternative
relations with the natural world.
Mastery vs. mimicry
In last week’s lecture we saw that from its etymological roots
in the classics technology becomes thoroughly modern in the notion of
technological mastery of nature. As we saw for Bernard Stiegler‘s
this mastery is both an expression of the condition of modernity and a
metaphysical project of mastery:
Technology becomes modern when metaphysics expresses and completes
itself as the project of calculative reason with a view to the mastery
and possession of nature. (p. 10)
In this weeks lecture we are going to rethink the notion of mastery
by examining a counter traditional within science and engineering –
mimicry. In broad terms, whilst notion of mastery assumes that the project
of technology is to ‘improve’ upon natural systems, mimicry
starts from the premise that the natural systems are already more complex,
and more elegant than human creations and hence goal is mimic ‘natural’
machines. So rather than view nature as a ‘calculable coherence
of forces’ sees nature as a set of evolving complex dynamics through
which to make new types of machines.
Exercise
7.1 Watch the two videos, available on the discussion site, entitled ‘Eva’
and ‘Kismet’. In both cases researchers are attempting to
model the perceptual abilities and learning capacities of existing organisms
in creating robotic systems that hove a degree of cognition. Both cases
the aim is for the robotic system to ‘evolve’ as it ‘learns’
from its surroundings and external stimuli. In what ways are these two
examples, consistent with the technical drive toward mastery, and in what
ways do they exhibit a more mimetic approach? Are these approaches in
tension or complementary?
Please read chapters 1 & 8 of Janine Benyus’ Biomimicry:
Innovation Inspired by Nature available on the course discussion
site.
Benyus presents a vision of bio-mimicry in which technological innovation
is infused with insights from biology in order to create more environmentally
sensitive technologies:
Now that we can synthesize what we need and re-arrange the genetic
alphabet to our liking, we have gained what we think of as autonomy.
Strapped to our juggernaut of technology, we fancy ourselves as gods,
very far from home indeed. … In reality, we haven’t escaped
the gravity of life at all. We are still beholden to ecological laws,
the same as any other life-form. … When we stare into nature’s
eyes, it takes our breath away, and in a good way, it bursts our bubble.
We realise that all our inventions have already appeared in nature in
more elegant form and at a lot less cost to the planet. (Benyus, 1997,
5)
Benyus’ introduction to bio-mimicry is interesting both because
of the way it outlines the possibilities of integrating engineering and
biology, but also for the ambiguities of her vision. At some points her
vision is consistent with the overall project of western technology toward
mastery of nature, whilst at other points she seems to point to a new,
more humble, vision of technology ‘working with nature’. It
is clear that she is inspired by nature, and by a sense of the need to
transform modern technological society to be more sensitive to the environment.
Yet she also seems to advocate deeply technocratic solutions to these
problems. Similarly her vision of biomimeticism encompasses technologies
that on the one hand simply take their inspiration from natural systems,
to more advanced modelling and synthetic recreation of natural systems.
Exercise
7.2: Use the online encyclopaedia ‘Wikipedia’ (http://en.wikipedia.org/)
to explore the breadth of current biomimetic thought. Search terms such
as ‘bionics’, ‘evolutionary computation’, ‘synthetic
biology’, ‘Evolutionary algorithm’ and ‘self organisation’.
In what ways do these new fields challenge the assumptions inherent in
modern technological endeavour?
In one sense the ambiguity in Benyus between ‘inspiration’
and ‘recreation’ is instructive. The NASA website dedicated
to ‘Biomimetics: Biologically-Inspired Technologies’ (http://ndeaa.jpl.nasa.gov/nasa-nde/biomimetics/bm-hub.htm)
positions biomimicry as a ‘natural’ extension of general human
inspiration in natural species. The site states:
"Humans
have always looked at nature for inspiration to making our life more
comfortable. The use of tweezers was probably one of the first such
tools where human adapted the shape and performance of birds’
beak. Evolution of biologically inspired technologies (having the moniker
Biomimetics) led to the emergence of such fields as artificial intelligence,
muscles, vision and others. These fields are making it possible to consider
developing prosthetics that feel and operate like the "real thing"
as well as engineering robots that look and behave as human and animals."
For NASA, biomimeticism is nothing new, indeed new prosthetics and forms
of artificial intelligence are simply another example of humans taking
‘inspiration’ from nature in building new technologies. The
site gives the example of the tweezer which is modelled on the shape of
the bird’s beak. Indeed, mimicry, it is claimed, is integral to
the survival of species, particularly the ability to adopt to environments
and develop protection from danger (e.g. camouflage). In this sense taking
inspiration from nature is positioned as necessary to human survival,
and thoroughly natural. This vision of biomimeticism is consistent both
with technological determinism and mastery we discussed last week.
There is, however something, revolutionary in Benyus’ account.
For the doctrine of mastery nature is imperfect, simple and basic. The
goal of technology is to build upon nature and to extend it in order to
improve the human condition and to enhance human performance. Benyus,
however, reverses this dualism. She says, that ‘all our inventions
have already appeared in nature in more elegant form’. For Benyus,
the goal of technology should not be to supersede nature but rather to
mimic it. For Benyus, natural systems are the most advanced and most elegant
and most advanced technologies, and hence serve as models for technical
innovation. It is here that her ambiguity between inspiration and recreation
becomes clear. Her vision of technology is more than simple inspiration
– but rather forms of technology that seek to model, imitate and
recreate natural systems.
Illustration 1. shows a non-poisonous snake in the centre mimicking the
colouring of a two poisonous snakes.
Two examples help here:
DNA-Nanotechnology
A key property of biological nanostructures is molecular recognition,
leading to self-assembly and the templating of atomic and molecular
structures. For example, it is well known that two complementary strands
of DNA will pair to form a double helix. DNA illustrates two features
of self-assembly. The molecules have a strong affinity for each other
and they form a predictable structure when they associate. Those who
wish to create defined nanostructures would like to develop systems
that emulate this behaviour. Thus, rather than milling down from the
macroscopic level, using tools of greater and greater precision (and
probably cost), they would like to build nanoconstructs from the bottom
up, starting with chemical systems. (Seeman & Belcher, 2002, 6451)
Spintronics
A multidisciplinary field whose central theme is the active manipulation
of spin degrees of freedom in solid-state systems. The term spin stands
for either the spin of a single electron s, which can be detected by
its magnetic moment 2g mBs ( mB is the Bohr magneton and g is the electron
g factor, in a solid generally different from the free-electron value
of g052.0023), or the average spin of an ensemble of electrons, manifested
by magnetization. The control of spin is then a control of either the
population and the phase of the spin of an ensemble of particles, or
a coherent spin manipulation of a single or a few-spin system. The goal
of spintronics is to understand the interaction between the particle
spin and its solid-state environments and to make useful devices using
the acquired knowledge. Fundamental studies of spintronics include investigations
of spin transport in electronic materials, as well as of spin dynamics
and spin relaxation. (Zutic et al, 2004, 323)
In
both DNA-nanotechnology and spintronics the goal is not only to take inspiration
from nature but to capitalise on existing natural systems, and to emulate
biological processes, in building machines. Thus in DNA-nanotechnology
the goal is to use the existing functionality of DNA to build new types
of nano-machines. Similarly in spintronics the goal is to utilise the
spin of electrons to create new kinds of electrical devices. In both cases
the relationship between technology and nature is changed. Rather than
aim to master nature, such technology aim to either capitalise on existing
biological examples or to direct natural systems in certain ways. There
is huge uncertainty here. The attempt to build machines using the functionality
of DNA is countered by the complexity of DNA’s existing functionality.
Similarly the goal of spintronics necessitates working with the massive
complexities inherent in the movement of electrons. In both cases then,
the goal is not to master these systems, but to work with them and direct
them in certain ways.
In both a key concept is self-organisation, which ‘refers to a
process in which the internal organization of a system, normally an open
system, increases automatically without being guided or managed by an
outside source. Self-organizing systems typically (though not always)
display emergent properties’. It is this attempt to direct self-organisation,
and to both predict and capitalise on such emergent properties that presents
such a challenge to conventional philosophies of technology. Robert Laughlin
(2005), expresses the challenges posed by this advanced science to traditional
concepts of mastery and control:
What we’re actually experiencing, of course, is a scientific
paradigm shift – a large-scale reorganisation in how we think
forced upon us by events. It is plain to anyone that [self-organising
systems] represents something new in the history of human interactions
with nature, and that turning point will require an invention. (p. 139)
Please read chapters 18 & 19 of Tim Ingold’s
The Perception of the Environment. In what ways does Ingold rethink technological
design?
In a sense then, we need new philosophical resources in thinking through
the philosophical implications of such technology and composing a philosophy
of technology adequate to these challenges.
Vitalism
The Routledge Encyclopaedia entry on vitalism is:
Vitalists hold that living organisms are fundamentally different from
non-living entities because they contain some non-physical element or
are governed by different principles than are inanimate things. In its
simplest form, vitalism holds that living entities contain some fluid,
or a distinctive ‘spirit’. In more sophisticated forms,
the vital spirit becomes a substance infusing bodies and giving life
to them; or vitalism becomes the view that there is a distinctive organization
among living things. Vitalist positions can be traced back to antiquity.
Aristotle’s explanations of biological phenomena are sometimes
thought of as vitalistic, though this is problematic. In the third century
BC, the Greek anatomist Galen held that vital spirits are necessary
for life. Vitalism is best understood, however, in the context of the
emergence of modern science during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
Mechanistic explanations of natural phenomena were extended to biological
systems by Descartes and his successors. Descartes maintained that animals,
and the human body, are ‘automata’, mechanical devices differing
from artificial devices only in their degree of complexity. Vitalism
developed as a contrast to this mechanistic view. Over the next three
centuries, numerous figures opposed the extension of Cartesian mechanism
to biology, arguing that matter could not explain movement, perception,
development or life. Vitalism has fallen out of favour, though it had
advocates even into the twentieth century. The most notable is Hans
Driesch (1867–1941), an eminent embryologist, who explained the
life of an organism in terms of the presence of an entelechy, a substantial
entity controlling organic processes. Likewise, the French philosopher
Henri Bergson (1874–1948) posited an élan vital to overcome
the resistance of inert matter in the formation of living bodies
Bergson is the most significant modern vitalist thinker. Whilst vitalism
has been long discredited scientifically as an explanation of the formation
of biological things, Bergson revives the spirit of vitalism in his thinking
about the intersection between the subject and the object. In Matter
and Memory Bergson is interested in understanding the relationship
between the material world and the world of image, perception and memory.
He sets out to prove that ‘… memory … is just the intersection
of mind and matter.’ (p. 13) and constructs a conception of the
image as an aggregate of the mental and the material. His philosophy is
a philosophy of mixtures in which things, images, perceptions, and ideas
are fundamental mixtures of mental and material substances. His interest
in memory is an interest in a materially composed past. To have a memory
of a thing is to have a physical remembrance of it.
There is a degree of communication between Bergson’s notion of
memory and the phenomenological notion of perception. Traditional histories
of philosophy often class Bergson’s conception of perception alongside
Merleau-Ponty’s as a search for a Kantian intuition or primordial
experience. It also appears that Merleau-Ponty was well schooled in Bergson’s
understanding of perception, and cites his work approvingly as an important
Discovery of the pre-human. Whilst both Bergson and Merleau-Ponty deal
in the realm of perception, only Bergson’s notion of materiality
troubles the Kantian universalism of phenomenology. Compare, for example
Merleau-Ponty’s, notion of matter’s self presentation to the
subject:
‘We see the things themselves, the world is what we see,’
begins Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s The Visible and the Invisible.
The opening line expresses the fundamental starting point for phenomenology,
namely, that the world gives itself to us, even if only with pretensions
of completeness, and that we open onto the things or matters themselves
with a basic perceptual faith that amounts to our immediate acceptance
of the being of things. This point of departure for phenomenology is,
in short, experience. (Steinbock, 1997, 127)
with Bergson’s conception of the material play:
Our daily life is spent among objects whose very presence invites us
to play a part… (Bergson, 1911b [1988], 95)
What is important here is that Bergson fundamentally decentres perception.
For phenomenologists, such as Merleau-Ponty, perception is the process
through which the human subject views and experiences an external world.
Whereas for Bergson the act of perception is double action undertaken
by both the subject and the object. In perception both the ‘subject’
and the ‘object’ move toward each other, and are changed
in the experience. Perception is formed not simply through a subjective
apprehension of the material world. Instead, the object ‘invites
us’ to perceive. The object has a certain capacity or agency for
invitation. It is with this notion of invitation that Bergson radically
redefines the quality of perceptive knowledge. Subjective knowledge
is not simply a cognitive organisation of perceptive impression. Rather,
knowledge is a fundamental mixture of both the mental and the material
as the object invites us to ‘play a part’. He states:
More generally, does not the fiction of an isolated object imply a kind
of absurdity, since the object borrows its physical properties from
the relations which it maintains with all others, and owes each of its
determinations, and consequently, its very existence to the place which
it occupies in the universe as a whole? Let us no longer say, then,
that our perceptions depend upon the molecular movements of the cerebral
mass. We must say rather that they vary with them, but that these movements
remain inseparably bound up with the rest of the material world. (p.
25)
Bergson notion of matter is a vitalist one. Matter is not a fundamental
and essential outside, but rather an active constituent of the object.
To perceive is thus to engage in the same active vitalism as matter itself.
It is ‘to vary with’ the object. In a sense what Bergson is
doing is to take the Aristotelian notion of vitalism – that there
exists an internal life force with biology to explain the creation and
appearance of different species – to apply to the non-organic. Though
perhaps, for Bergson, vitalism has lost it spirituality and magic, he
uses vitalism to make an ontological claim about the nature of matter.
His concept of the élan vital or ‘vital impetus’ is
a complex reaction against the notion that the trajectory of evolution
is already laid out. Rather the élan vital is a kind of vital force
which drives evolution ever onwards in the perpetual creation of new species
and individuals.
Therefore the importance of a vitalist conception of matter for a philosophy
of technology is in the way in alters the ontological basis upon which
technical production is achieved. In as much as Ingold suggests that weaving
a basket involves a sensuous and muscular negotiation of forces between
the wicker and the weaver vitalists, and particularly Bergson, would suggest
that in some senses this material negotiation is on the basis of the animate
capacities of material. To be sure, Bergson does not suggest that matter
is imbued with the same vital force as ‘life itself’, but
rather that matter is somehow caught up in the ongoing and undetermined
evolution of life and material forms. For Bergson material forms and different
forms of life are simply momentary stabilisations of this vital force.
Applied biologically, Bergson suggests that the human species, though
unique, is simply a temporary stabilisation of this vital force. Similarly
applied to the non-organic world, Bergson would claim that in geological
time the great features of the earth are perpetually evolving and changing.
In a sense then goal of technology, for Bergson, is to work with this
fundamental evolution in creating momentary stabilisations.
Think:
how does a Bergsonian conception of evolution relate
to bio-mimetic technologies? How does this help (or not?) to think through
what is at stake in the attempt to direct self-organisation or self-replication
in the creation of new technologies? How does would Bergson view the notion
of artificial evolution?
Radical Constructivism
In the same way that Bergsonian vitalism is directed against a mechanistic
interpretation of evolution the ‘essential claim [of Radical Constructivism]
is that organisms interpret their environment and are not merely passive
objects of natural selection, as emphasised by contemporary Darwinian
evolutionary biology’ (Bains, 2001, 141). Von Glasersfeld defines
the key tenants of radical constructivism as:
• Knowledge is not passively received either through the senses
or by way of communication;
• Knowledge is actively built up by the cognizing subject.
• The function of cognition is adaptive, in the biological sense
of the term, tending towards fit or viability;
• Cognition serves the subject’s organization of the experiential
world, not the discovery of an objective ontological reality. (von Glasersfeld,
1995, p. 51)
Please read Jakob von Uexküll’s Stroll
Through the Worlds of Animals and Men (1934) available on the MAVE discussion
site.
Jakob von Uexküll’s seminal work Stroll Through the Worlds
of Animals and Men is a key starting point in the development of
Radical Constructivism. Von Uexküll’s notion of the Umwelt
or perceptual self-world of the animal, bird and organism has also been
developed in cybernetics, bio-semiotics and artificial intelligence. In
his (1934) Stroll Through the Worlds of Animals and Men he develops
a notion of the Umwelt, how the world appears to the animal. For von Uexküll
the body, both human and nonhuman, is enfolded by the senses, and thus
each being operates within an ontologically unique perceptual world, or
Umwelt. For example:
Perhaps [the Umwelt] should be called a stroll into unfamiliar worlds;
worlds strange to us but known to other creatures, manifold and varied
as the animals themselves. The best time to set out on such an adventure
is on a sunny day. The place, a flower-strewn meadow, humming with insects,
fluttering with butterflies. Here we may glimpse the worlds of the lowly
dwellers of the meadow. … A new world comes into being …
the world as it appears to animals themselves, not as it appears to
us. This we may call the phenomenal world or the self-world of the animal.
(p. 5)
The importance of Umwelt is that is signals an attention to the way that
animals, birds and organisms interpret their world, almost in composing
a phenomenology of animal experience. Importantly Von Uexküll develops
his notion of the Umwelt for all manner of living creatures – mammals,
fish, birds and simpler single beings such as larvae and cell organisms,
sketching depictions of the Umwelt of, for example, the scallop and the
pea-weevil larvae.
It is clear that there is a certain romanticism of the animal at work
here. This is the romanticism of the naturalist, and the sunny day with
butterflies over the meadow. Though Deleuze and Guattari (1987) regard
von Uexküll, positively, as the grandfather of ethology, there is
also a deep Kantianism to his perceptual schema. However, this is tempered
by the fact that his notion of the Umwelt is a combination of both active
and perceptive capacities of the being. It is perpetually changing with
the being, as it perceives and acts upon its world.
The significance of von Uexküll’s work is that his proposition
that animals and other creatures operate as interpretive agents of the
world, both perceiving and interpreting their own worlds, signals the
autonomy of even very simple creatures such as larvae and bacteria.
Von
Uexküll’s ethological theory of meaning has, therefore been
developed as a theory of proto-semiosis or bio-semiosis – a consideration
of the very basic ‘proto-sign-processes’ at play in the interaction
between, for example, bacteria and its world. Similarly von Uexküll’s
notion of the Umwelt has become an important tool in the development of
artificial life and robotic systems, in the analysis of the perceptual
capacities of such systems. For example:
AI has come (or returned) to an Uexküllian view of meaning in which
signs/representations are viewed not as referring to specific external
objects, but embedded in functional circles along which the interaction
of agent and environment is organised/structures. (Ziemke, 2001, 197)
Such a theory or meaning, radically transforms the presumed goal of mechanical
and cognitive autonomy of such AI research. Rather than conceive such
intelligent systems as autonomous, robotic agents, an Uexküllian
conception of the Umwelt of the robot, suggests that intelligent systems
are enwrapped in their own environment. Von Uexküll, therefore presents
a complex picture of the perceptive autonomy of biological systems –
a kind of relational autonomy, in which the being is sensually entwined
in an autonomous Umwelt.
Indeed, for von Uexküll this notion of ‘autonomy’ is
critical to his definition of ‘life’. In opposition to Darwinian
mechanism, which would suggest that organisms are ‘passive objects
of natural selection’ von Uexküll develops a notion of ‘relational
autonomy’, in which the organism is inexorably located within it
environment, and yet autonomous. Von Uexküll maintains a strong distinction
between organisms and mechanisms on the basis of their relative autonomy.
For von Uexküll, machines lack the autonomy necessary to qualify
as living organisms, acting according to external plans. Similarly, mechanisms,
for von Uexküll, are without any ability to self-regenerate in the
same manner as a living or natural systems. Therefore, though informational
exchange is key to ‘intelligent’ mechanical systems, such
exchange does not qualify, according to von Uexküll, as full semiosis,
nor the formation of a robot self-world.
Von Uexküll’s distinction, between organisms and mechanisms,
is, however, challenged by current research in biomimeticism, artificial
intelligence and synthetic biology. Research in artificial intelligence
systems is concerned with the creation of suitably complex algorithms
which would bring to ‘life’ mechanical and robotic systems.
Alternatively the bio-mimetic vision is to harness the very intelligence
and perceptive world of existing biological systems. Bio-mimeticsm aims
to design biological machines that both autonomous in an Uexküllian
sense and able to organise, replicate and regenerate themselves.
Think:
How does von Uexküll’s notion of Umwelt and relational autonomy
relate to current developments in biomimeticsm and artificial intelligence?
Similarly how does von Uexküll help in unpacking whether the products
of such research are real or artificial, alive or dead, animate or inanimate?
A resource to help in this is Tom Ziemke’s useful summary available
on the discussion site.
References
Bains, P., 2001: Umwelten. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 137-167.
Bechtel, W & Robert C. R., 1998: Vitalism. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge
Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.
Bergson, H., 1911 [1988]: Creative Evolution. Dover Publications,
New York.
Bergson, H., 1908 [1991] Matter and Memory. Zone Books, New York.
Laughlin, R. B., 2005: A Different Universe: Reinventing Physics from
the Bottom Down. Basic Books, New York.
Merleau-Ponty, M., 1962: The Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge,
London.
Seeman, N. C. & Belcher, A. M., 2002: Emulating biology: building
nanostructures from the bottom up. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, 99(2), 6451-6455.
von Glasersfeld, E., 1995: Radical Constructivism – A Way of
Knowing and Learning. London: Falmer Press.
Zutic, I., Fabian, J. & Das Sarma, S., 2004: Spintronics: Fundamentals
and Applications. Reviews of Modern Physics, 76(2), 323-410.
Web notes by Mathew Kearnes June 2005 |