I. Introduction to Friedrich Holderlin
The next figure we will look at is Friedrich Holderlin.
Holderlin was one of the German Romantics who started off very concerned
at human separation from nature and sought to overcome it through art.
However, as his thought developed he became increasingly critical of the
attempt to overcome our separation from nature. By looking at his thought
we can see some interesting problems with any such attempts.
Brief
biography:
As well as writing poetry, Holderlin wrote a number
of theoretical essays (mostly from 1794 to 1800), which largely survive
only in fragmentary form. In addition Hölderlin wrote dramas and
a novel Hyperion (published 1797-1799), while some of his poems are better
described as ‘hymns’ – that is, they are songs which
celebrate or praise the gods. During his earlier years (esp. up until
1800), Hölderlin was a very close interlocutor of Schelling and Hegel.
Yet in 1802, Hölderlin began to show signs of mental disturbance
and in 1807 he was admitted to psychiatric hospital. Discharged as incurable,
he continued, tragically, to suffer mental distress for the rest of his
life and had to be looked after.
II. Holderlin's philosophical fragments.
These are a range of letters, jottings, and short pieces
which set out Holderlin's general idea of nature, which goes on to inform
his later reflections on our separation from nature and how/whether we
can regain unity with it. These fragments are very abstract and you can
skip this subsection if you like!
Holderlin wrote many of these fragments in response to another
German philosopher writing at the time, J. G. Fichte.
Fichte in turn was responding to Kant. Kant had argued that
all knowledge is shaped, actively, by the knowing subject. Fichte wanted
a more systematic study of how the subject shapes the forms of its own
knowledge. He thought that all knowledge necessarily involves self-consciousness
(consciousness of myself as a subject), because as knowing is active I
must at some level always know that I am engaged in it. So the basic fact
is that each of us is always self-conscious, and all the various ways
we know things must be derived from this constant. However, Fichte argued,
when we are aware of the external world (nature) this is a limit on our
self-consciousness, each of us is aware of something that is not us.
We therefore engage in an infinite striving, as he saw it, to transform
nature and make it into something through which we can be aware of ourselves
again. He spoke, rather dismayingly, about the human need to cultivate
marshes and wild areas and make into places that reflect human consciousness.
Holderlin's early fragments engage with these claims of
Fichte's. Please have a look now at his fragment called 'Being Judgement
Possibility' from 1795 (in the reader). Don't worry if you find it utterly
puzzling at this point - one of our aims is to just to get more familiar
with Holderlin's way of writing and thinking.
Holderlin is making several points here (against Fichte):
(i) All consciousness involves a 'limitation' - whenever
I am conscious of any object then I am at some level aware that this object
is not me. But if as Fichte thinks self-consciousness is not initially
limited, then it cannot be a form of consciousness at all - it
cannot be a subject.
(ii) This basic, unlimited, reality cannot be said to be
self-conscious as this already involves a sense of difference between
two 'selves' (the one that's comparing and the one being compared). Self-consciousness
already involves reflection, judgement, something less than absolute unlimitedness.(iii)
The basic reality must therefore be something not conscious, unified in
a very deep way. It is something which precedes consciousness,
precedes the relation of subject and object. It is an original unity
of subject and object, 'the blessed unity of being'.
(iv) This unitary being cannot be known. We cannot be conscious
of it because whenever we are conscious, we're conscious of objects,
things that aren't the same as us. But this sense of difference is lacking
from unitary being.
(v) This original being, the basis of everything, is nature.
Why does Holderlin identify this original being with nature?
He is relying on the ancient Greek understanding of nature (physis)
- Holderlin was very immersed in the Greeks - as that which 'loves to
hide'. Because being is unknowable, always disappearing, breaking up into
separate subjects and objects, it can be said to 'love to hide' and so
identified with nature.
Or as J. Bernstein explains this: 'nature as the ground
[that is, the basis, origin] of the human cannot appear because it would
have to be judged, but if judged, then it is already in a state of dispersion'
(Bernstein, 'Introduction' to Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics,
p. xxvi).
Overall conclusion of this early fragment: Nature is the
origin, the basis of all of us as humans; but this is not nature in the
usual sense, that is, as an object (or set of objects) which humans encounter.
It is something deeper, a unity of human subjects and objects.
Because it is mysterious, unknowable, this deeper nature is divine, it
is something deserving of awe and reverence.
III. Holderlin's views of nature in his novel Hyperion.
For
Holderlin, then, we cannot know nature, yet we have some awareness of
it as our basis and origin; we feel separated from it, and are always
nostalgic for the nature we have lost. Because we are cultural, historical
beings, we are always cut off from nature (where everything about being
cultural is fundamentally a matter of being engaged in making judgements
upon objects). [This is a variant on the general German Romantic idea
that we get cut off from nature by becoming too reflective, too
immersed in thought. Holderlin's ideas here also recall Steven
Vogel's discussion of the way in which humanity seems separate from nature,
artificial.]
However, for Holderlin, we endlessly strive to be reunited
with nature. 'To be united with nature, with a unique infinite totality,
is the goal of all our aspirations' he says in the preface to Hyperion.
Holderlin thought that the role of art was to depict humanity
as engaged in this striving. This is the closest we can get to knowing
nature - observing our own efforts to rejoin with it.
Please now read the section from Hyperion that is
your main piece of reading for this week. It comes from the very start
of the novel and is written, as you can see, in a series of letters which
Holderlin is writing to his friend Bellarmin. You could think about the
following questions:
Think
(i) How does Holderlin depict the effort to reunite
with nature here? How does he characterise our separation from it?
(ii) What do you think of Holderlin's very strange language
and style? What does it evoke - how do you think it's connected with his
attempt to portray nature itself as best as he can?
(iii) What connections, if any, can you see between
this section of the novel and the early fragment that you looked at above?
(iv) How do you think Holderlin's thoughts on human
separation from nature might bear on the problem that Steven Vogel raised
(see block one) - i.e. that if humanity is part of nature, then it seems
that nothing humans do can properly be counted as 'unnatural' or 'artificial'?
Does Holderlin have an answer to this question, or does the question pose
a problem for his thought, in your view?
IV. Holderlin's views on tragedy
Holderlin went on to develop his thoughts on our separation
from nature by thinking more closely about ancient Greek tragedy.
The last piece of reading by him that we are looking at this
week is his very short fragment 'The significance of tragedy' (from 1802).
Please have a quick read of it now.
What on earth does it mean? It's very condensed, but here's
part of what's going on here: the tragic hero strives for unity
with nature, but is engulfed by nature, destroyed, reduced to nothing
(to a zero = 0) - this destruction of the hero depicts a moment
of reconciliation with nature, where the 'sign' is absorbed back into
original unity with nature (and therefore nature at this point appears
'straight out' - it appears fully - rather than only 'in its weakness',
i.e. as divided up into the hero and the world opposing him).
Holderlin spent a lot of time obsessively writing and rewriting
a tragedy in the ancient Greek style, about a man called Empedocles, who
sought unity with nature and eventually committed suicide to achieve it.
He sought to escape from individuality, from separation from nature. There
is a great article about this by Francoise Dastur in Philosophy and
Tragedy - see below for full details. She says that if Empedocles
'does not die, then the divine dimension will be lost, the totality will
become particularity, the intensity of life will crystallise in a particular
being and thus there will be ... no sphere simultaneously human and divine,
but a total flatness of a "human, too human" life' (p. 84).
Holderlin redrafted his tragedy The Death of Empedocles
several times - he got dissatisfied with how he'd depicted Empedocles'
death. He came to think that there were two solutions to separation from
nature - (1) the Greek, which is to dissolve yourself and leave the world,
(2) the 'Hesperian', which is to lead a living death, to endure
separation from nature. This is the modern way. It involves putting up
with the tension of being cut off from nature, the inevitable feeling
of limitation.
Now, crucially, Holderlin came to see this as better because
he came to think that the desire to reunite with nature is hybristic
- that is, it's arrogant (from the Greek word hybris). This is
a really important criticism of the desire for unity with nature, which
bears back on his own earlier work and on the whole German Romantic project.
The basic point for Holderlin now is that the attempt to overcome separation
from nature is itself arrogant, human-centred. Why does he think this?
We can break down his train of thought into the following stages (he himself
didn't, but it's helpful for us to try to get some analytical clarity
at this point):
(a) If, initially, humanity is truly one with nature, then
their separation cannot come from any activity on the part of humanity
just as such. The separation must arise from nature, with which
humanity is at this point united. Nature must divide itself –
into humanity on the one hand, and an objectified version of itself on
the other. As human beings, to construe ourselves as responsible for this
division is (paradoxically) to go on thinking of ourselves as beings who
are separate from nature as a whole - this assumption being shown in that
we are presuming ourselves to be capable of acting independently
of this whole.
(b) It follows, Hölderlin thinks, that it is not an
appropriate response to try to overcome the separation– to try to
do something about it, to actively strive for the restoration of the earlier
unity. To suppose that we can do anything against this separation is anthropocentric,
in that it continues to see humans as capable of independent action, and
action that goes against what nature itself has done (i.e. divided itself).
We've been separated from nature by its power alone, and hence
it isn't within our power to overcome the separation.
(c) The appropriately modest response is to endure separation,
to wait for nature itself to bring about a change in its mode of being.
Our best response, as individuals in the modern age, is just to experience
and undergo the suffering of being separated from nature.
(d) So, the whole Romantic attempt to use art to restore
unity with nature (even in the minimal way the early Holderlin thought
- by depicting striving for unity) is misguided. It's anthropocentric,
assuming we can do something to gain unity (via art). Nonetheless,
Holderlin does still think there is an important role for art - but a
different one. Art can give recognition to the suffering of our modern
fate. The function of art is to bear witness to this suffering. Art can
only do this if it recognises the necessity of the suffering, as deriving
from nature itself.The appropriate kind of art for this role, Holderlin
thought, was lyric poetry - which is what he wrote from now on
- not tragedy or drama.
[If you've enjoyed the Holderlin material, you might like
to read some of his poems at this point which are available in a translation
from German by Michael Hamburger - his introduction to the volume is also
very good. Especially worth reading are the poems 'The Ister', 'The Rhine',
'Germania', 'Remembrance', 'Patmos' and 'As On a Holiday'.]
V. Interesting ways in which Holderlin's philosophy relates to ecology/environmental
thought
(a) The relation between humanity and nature. If humans
are cultural beings, who lead a rather artificial, intellectualised, life,
then are they non-natural?
Holderlin's answer seems to be - they are both natural and
non-natural, because humanity is the place where nature divides itself
up, where nature turns against itself. The condition of
being non-natural - opposed to the rest of nature - is itself something
inflicted on us by nature. This is a very intriguing view of humanity.
Holderlin takes it partly from one of the choruses in Sophocles' tragedy
Antigone where man is said to be the 'uncanny' being, the 'violent'
being.
(2) The idea that we cannot overcome separation from nature,
but must accept disenchantment.
Rather than it being the attempt to re-enchant nature which
is aligned with environmental concerns, Holderlin thinks that it is the
acceptance of disenchantment, of separation, of meaninglessness,
which reflects a more properly 'environmental' stance, in the sense that
this acceptance is the properly non-anthropocentric attitude.
Question:
one of last year's students said (rightly, I think!) that Holderlin's
thought is like deep ecology, but in reverse. How do you think this might
be so?
- Here you could think about - what sort of attitudes
is Holderlin advocating? How do these contrast to the attitudes which
deep ecology thinks that we should adopt?
Another question: what, do you think, are the practical
implications of taking a resigned attitude as Holderlin advises? Does
this amount to a rather worrying acceptance of the destruction and damaging
of the environment that's going on all around us - i.e. is Holderlin recommending
'quietism'? Or is it the case that, even if what he advises is quietism
on one level, on another level it is a shift in attitude which might ultimately
be best for the environment?
In thinking about these questions, do bear in mind that
the ideas considered this week are difficult, especially those of Hölderlin;
you do not need to be worried if it takes you a while to feel that you
are getting to grips with them.
For further reading on Holderlin, including the full details
of the texts by Bernstein and Dastur and the other Holderlin pieces referred
to above, please see the general course bibliography.
Web notes by Alison Stone updated March 2005
|