I. Environmental ethics, meta-ethics and intrinsic value
New environmental ethic
Over the last few weeks we have considered the moral considerability of
the non-human world: How far should we push the bounds of moral considerability
– persons, humans, sentient beings, living things, ecosystems, beyond
this? Proponents of the need for a ‘new environmental ethic’
often hold that to hold an environmental ethic is to hold that we should
push the boundaries further to include non-humans.
One central formulation of an environmental ethic is that which puts
it in terms of ‘intrinsic value’ of non-human nature.
To hold a environmental ethic is to hold that non human beings and states
of affairs in the natural world have intrinsic value.
From A. Naess and G. Sessions
The Deep Ecology Platform
- The well-being and flourishing of human and nonhuman life on Earth
have
value in themselves (synonyms: inherent worth, intrinsic value, inherent
value).
These values are independent of the usefulness of the nonhuman world
for human
purposes.
- Richness and diversity of life-forms contribute to the realization
of these
values and are also values in themselves.
What is meant by ‘intrinsic value’?
- Non instrumental value – ‘ends in themselves’. Objects,
activities and states of affair have instrumental value insofar as they
are a means to some other end. They have intrinsic value if they are
ends in themselves. Under pain of an infinite regress, not everything
can have only instrumental value.
a). Non-instrumental is sometimes predicated of objects, states and
activities that an agent pursues:
e.g. a person climbs mountains for its own sake; the person might
also be said to value for their own sake; or that he admires states
of these for their own sake, the beauty of mountains.
b) To assert a being is an end it itself and not just a means to
an end is to assert that it has ethical standing (Kant).
A central move in much environmental ethics has been to extend ethical
standing beyond persons. To say that elephants, wolves, plants matter
in the sense that their good must be considered in making choices
is to assign standing to them. (To say one values climbing mountains,
the beauty of mountains or mountains themselves for their own sake
need not involve the ascription of any such standing.)
- Intrinsic value is used to refer to the value an object has solely
in virtue of its ”intrinsic properties” i.e. its non relational
properties.
‘To say a kind of value is ”intrinsic” means merely
that the question whether a thing possesses it, and in what degree
it possesses it, depends solely on the intrinsic nature of the thing
in question. (G. E. Moore)
- Intrinsic value is used as a synonym for ”objective value”
i.e. value that an object possesses independently of the valuations
of valuers. To claim that non human beings have intrinsic value in this
sense is not to make an ethical but a meta ethical claim. It is to assert
a form of realism about ethical claims which denies the view that the
source of all value lies in valuers in their attitudes, preferences
and so on.
Meta-ethics
Proponents of that new environmental ethic often claim that changes in
ethical theory will require a change in our meta-ethical theories at the
same time: ‘A radical change in a theory sometimes forces a change
in meta-theory’ (Richard Routley ‘Is there a need for a new,
an environmental, ethic?’ in Light and Rolston p.51). The central
reason for this shift to meta-ethics is as just noted the third sense
of intrinsic value.
Meta-ethics is concerned with the status and nature
of the ethical claims we make.
As such meta-ethics deals not with substantive questions in
ethics but with questions about ethics.
Meta-ethical questions:
A. Are ethical utterances assertions that can be true or false?
Some answers to that question:
1. No
Non-cognitivism: Ethical statements are not assertions
about the way the world is. They are not true or false, since there is
nothing for them to be true or false of.
Expressivism
The most influential version of non-cognitivism is expressivism. Ethical
utterances are expressions of the speaker's attitudes or commitments towards
the world. They do not state facts, they express attitudes to the facts.
The most influential version of expressivism is emotivism (Ayer, Stevenson).
For the emotivist, ethical propositions have no factual content. Emotivists
argue that moral utterances evince our attitudes. Saying ‘X is good’
is like saying ‘Hurrah for X!’; saying ‘X is bad’
is like saying ‘Boo for X!’.
2. Yes
a) Error theory: Normative claims are assertions which
are either true or false, but in fact they are all false (Mackie).
b) Ethical Realism
Ethical statements are descriptions of states of the world and, in virtue
of being so they are, they are like other fact stating assertions, true
or false. The job of ethical judgements to track properties in the world,
to get something right about the way the world is. It is not the case
that all moral statement are false (vs. error theory)
Versions of ethical realism
Naturalism: Ethical facts are natural facts. The moral
properties that ethical statements describe are properties we can specify
using a naturalistic language. For example, some versions of utilitarianism
– an act that maximises happiness is the right act.
Non-naturalism: There are ethical facts but they are
not natural facts of the kind that could be the object of the natural
sciences. Goodness is a non-natural property of things and events. (G.E.
Moore and the intuitionists.)
Other related meta-ethical questions
B. Reason and ethics:
Are ethical judgements open to rational justification? Could we expect
all rational agents to converge in their moral judgements?
C. Logic of ethical concepts:
What are the logical properties of ethical concepts? What is the conceptual
relationship between general ethical concepts - good, bad, right and wrong
- and particular concepts - courageous, cowardly, kind, cruel, just, unjust
and the like?
D. Relation of ethics and actions:
How are ethical judgements connected with actions? Is the case that to
accept an ethical judgement is necessarily to be motivated to act upon
it?
II. Sources and Objects of Value
It is often assumed a non-cognitivist meta ethics entails that non humans
can have only instrumental value.
Meta ethical argument against an environmental ethic:
- To claim that items in the non human world have intrinsic values
commits one to a realist view of values;
- A realist view of values is indefensible;
- Hence the non human world contains nothing of intrinsic value.
Exercise:
Should the argument be accepted? Which premise, if any,
should be rejected?
Is premise 1 correct?
One standard response within the environmental ethics literature has
been to reject the second premise. This is a central source of the tendency
to forms of ethical realism in environmental philosophy. However, it is
not clear that we need to reject this premise (although there maybe good
independent reasons to do so). It is possible to reject the first premise.
Against the first premise: the premise is based on a confusion of claims
about the source of values with claims about their object.
The expressivist claims that the only source of value are the evaluative
attitudes of humans. This does not entail that the only ultimate objects
of value are the states of human beings.
(Likewise, to be a realist about the source of value, i.e. to claim that
whether or not something has value does not depend on the attitudes of
valuers, is compatible with a thoroughly anthropocentric view of the object
of value that the only things which do in fact have value are humans and
their states, such that a world without humans would have no value whatsoever.)
To illustrate the point consider emotivism:
For the emotivist evaluative utterances merely evince the speaker’s
attitudes with the purpose of changing the attitudes of the hearer. They
state no facts.
“X is intrinsically good” asserts that the speaker approves
of X intrinsically, and acts emotively to make the hearer or hearers likewise
approve of X intrinsically. (Stevenson)
However there are no reasons why the emotivist should not fill the X place
by entities and states of the non human world.
Let H! operator express hurrah attitudes and B! express boo attitudes.
Her ultimate values might for example include the following:
H! (The existence of natural ecosystems)
B! (The destruction of natural ecosystems by humans).
H! (My great grand children live in a world without poverty).
H! (Rain forests exist after the extinction of the human species) (vs.
last man’s vandalism)
H!(the possible world in which humans never came into existence)
To claim that non-humans have intrinsic value in the sense of having
non-instrumental value does not commit you to a realist view of ethics.
III. Values and Non relational Properties
In its second sense intrinsic value refers to the value an object has
solely in virtue of its ”intrinsic properties ie. its non relational
properties.
What is meant by ”non relational properties”? The non relational
properties of an object are those that persist regardless of the existence
or non existence of other objects (weak interpretation) or can be characterized
without reference to other objects (strong interpretation).
Some properties in environmental valuation are non-relational in both
senses. eg. ‘rarity’, ‘diversity’.
Exercise:
Why is ‘rarity’ a relational property?
Can relational properties have a place in an environmental ethic which
holds non humans have intrinsic value?
Here is an argument that has been used to suggest that they cannot:
- To hold an environmental ethic is to hold that natural objects have
intrinsic value.
- The values objects have in virtue of their relational properties,
e.g. their rarity, cannot be intrinsic values.
- Hence, the value objects have in virtue of their relational properties
have no place in an environmental ethic.
Exercise:
Is this argument convincing?
I do not think it is. This argument commits a fallacy of equivocation
(an apparently valid argument which is invalid since it uses the same
term in different senses in different premises).
• In premise 1, the term intrinsic value is used in its first sense
– to refer to non-instrumental value.
• In premise 2 it is used in a different second sense – to
refer to the value an object has in virtue of its non-relational properties.
The senses are distinct.. We might value an object in virtue of its relational
properties, for example its rarity, without thereby seeing it as having
only instrumental value for human satisfactions.
We need to distinguish:
- values objects can have in virtue of their relations to other objects;
and
- values objects can have in virtue of their relations to human beings.
The second set of values is a proper subset of the first. Moreover,
the second set of values is still not co extensive with
-
values objects can have in virtue of being instrumental for human
satisfaction.
An object might have value in virtue of its relation with human beings
without thereby being of only instrumental value for humans. To say
“x has value because it is untouched by humans” is to
say that it has value in virtue of a relation it has to humans and
their activities. Wilderness might have value in virtue of our absence.
However, the value is not necessarily possessed by wilderness in virtue
of its instrumental usefulness for the satisfaction of human desires.
IV. Objective Value and the Natural World
The claim that nature has non instrumental value does not commit one
to an realist meta-ethics. But there might be other reasons particularly
pertinent in the field of environmental ethics that would lead us to hold
an realist account of value. I show in this section that there are.
The ethical realist holds that the evaluative properties of objects are
real properties of objects, that is, that they are properties that objects
possess independently of the valuations of valuers.
Are good reasons for believing that there are objective values in a strong
sense: are there evaluative properties that can be characterized without
reference to the experiences of human observers and valuers?
Part of the pull for strong realism in the environmental sphere lies
in a broadly Aristotelian observation that there is a sense in which we
can talk of what it is for natural entities to flourish and what is good
and bad for them without this being dependent upon human interests.
Consider the gardener’s use of the phrase “x is good for
greenfly”. The term “good for” can be understood in
two distinct ways.
- To refer to what is conducive to the destruction of greenfly, as
in “detergent sprays are good for greenfly”,
- To describe what causes greenfly to flourish, as in “mild winters
are good for greenfly”.
The term “good for” in the first use describes what is instrumentally
good for the gardener: given the ordinary gardener’s interest in
the flourishing of her rosebushes, detergent sprays satisfy that interest.
The second use describes what is instrumentally good for the greenfly,
quite independently the gardener’s interests. This instrumental
goodness is possible in virtue of the fact that greenflies are the sorts
of things that can flourish or be injured. In consequence they have their
own goods that are independent of both human interests and any tendency
they might have to produce in human observers feelings of approval or
disapproval. What beings have such goods?
A being, of whose good it is meaningful to talk, is one who can meaningfully
be said to be well or ill, to thrive, to flourish, be happy or miserable...The
attributes, which go along with the meaningful use of the phrase ”the
good of X”, may be called biological in a broad sense. By this I
do not mean that they were terms, of which biologists make frequent use.
“Happiness” and “welfare” cannot be said to belong
to the professional vocabulary of biologists. What I mean by calling the
terms “biological” is that they are used as attributes of
beings, of whom it is meaningful to say they have a life. The question
“What kinds or species of being have a good?” is therefore
broadly identical with the question “What kinds or species of being
have a life”. (Von Wright)
Question:
Even if living things have goods in this sense does
it give us reasons for moral concern for them?
Intrinsic value and moral considerability
It is standard in much environmental literature to argue that possession
of goods does entail moral considerability: 'moral standing or considerability
belongs to whatever has a good of its own' (Attfield 1987, p.21) However,
this claim demands an argument. It is possible to talk in an objective
sense of what constitutes the goods of entities, without making any claims
that these ought to be realized. Our gardener knows what it is for greenfly
to flourish, recognizes they have their own goods, and has a practical
knowledge of what is good for them. No moral injunction follows. 'Y is
a good of X' does not immediately entail 'Y ought to be realized' (Taylor
1986 pp.71-2).
How might this gap be closed?
Possible arguments:
In week 5 we discussed one line of argument and possible problems with
it. Here is another line of argument.
Rolston: Since for any living being x there are objects and states of
affairs y1...yn that are of value to x, it follows that x values y1...yn.
By consistency if we value ourselves in virtue of being valuing agents
then we have to extend this to all living things. (Rolston, 1988)
Exercise:
Is this a good line of argument?
Here is a worry I have about the argument. The inference from 'y is of
value to x' to 'x values y' looks fallacious. There are differences in
the logical properties of the two types of sentence:
- 'y is of value to a' is extensional i.e. if y is of value to a, and
y=z, then z is of value to a;
- 'a values y' is intensional i.e. it is not the case that if a values
y and y=z then a values z'.
Example: 'Joseph is of great value to Martha' - unbeknownst to her he
has assisted her through her education. Since Joseph is the local priest,
it follows that 'the local priest is of great value to Martha'. But 'Martha
values the unknown benefactor who has assisted her through her education'
does not entail 'Martha values Joseph' or 'Martha values the local priest'.
She may despise Joseph and loath the clergy.
Whether or not something is of value to someone depends on the nature
of the object, its capacities to contribute to the flourishing of a being
however that is defined. Whether an object is valued by someone depends
upon the nature of the person's beliefs about and attitudes towards the
object. Valuing appears to require certain cognitive and affective capacities
that are not displayed by nonrational living things.
Exercise:
In my chapter ‘Meta-ethics’ in D. Jamieson
ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy I discuss other possible
ways of understanding the relation of the goods of non-human nature to
human ethical sensibilities. Read that chapter and consider if you think
any of these arguments are convincing.
|