What is "holistic environmental ethics"?
Holism, or collectivism, as it is sometimes called in this
context, can mean a number of different things and can be interpreted
in a variety of ways (and it is in these multiple interpretations that
confusions can easily arise). In most general terms - and unsurprisingly!
- holists or collectivists focus on wholes or collectives rather than
individuals. The first question here, then, must be "what sort of
wholes?" Some examples of the possible kinds of wholes are: family,
community, society, state and in environmental ethics, species, ecosystem
and biosphere.
Generally speaking, again, such holism has two strands which
are not necessarily related, but which are usually found together:
- a descriptive strand, where the integrity or cohesion of the whole
is emphasised
- an evaluative strand, where the significance, and in this case the
moral significance of the whole is emphasised.
This position contrasts with that of individualists, who either challenge
the cohesion of such wholes or their value. You may remember, for instance,
Margaret Thatcher's famous claim that "there is no such thing as
society". There are, of course, collections of individuals, she was
suggesting; but they do not cohere into a whole which we can talk about
as some kind of entity. One might hold that such holes exist but that
they are not the primary site of value.
An ethical holist will argue that wholes are morally considerable; and
often that the whole has ethical priority over its parts. In social and
political philosophy, this may mean espousing the view that the good of
an individual can be sacrificed for the benefit of society. A thoroughgoing
individualist would not concede this, maintaining that the individual
good should never be sacrificed for, and may need protecting from, society.
So, if that's a sketch of ethical holism, what's holistic environmental
ethics? Well, rather than beginning from individual organisms, holistic
environmental ethics usually begins from ecosystems, or sometimes as we
shall see, with an idea of "the land". Individual organisms
are parts of this whole. As part of a whole, they are relatively insignificant.
Their significance lies in what they contribute to the whole - their ecological
function - rather than on whether they are rational, sentient etc. It
is the system, not the individual which is of primary value. Indeed, this
emphasis (as we shall see) may mean that some states which are of positive
disvalue in many individualistic approaches to ethics are of positive
value in holistic ethics - such as suffering and disease.
I want to begin this section by looking at what is often cited as the
foundational work in holistic environmental ethics, Aldo Leopold's A Sand
County Almanac (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1949) (I am not sure the
description of the book as "the bible of the contemporary environmental
movement" as it is introduced in the Zimmermann collection would
withstand much scrutiny!)
Leopold: A Sand County Almanac
I recommend that you just sit down and read this book in a sitting or
two. Far from being an academic tome, A Sand County Almanac is a collection
of autobiographical and philosophical essays. It was taken up enthusiastically
in the late 1970s and onwards by those who espoused a holistic version
of environmental ethics.
Reading 1
Aldo Leopold: 'The Land Ethic' in Light and Rolston ed. Pp.38-46. Excerpts
can be found here
Leopold works with a model, common to ethical writing, of a continually
expanding circle of ethical concern. At one time, he suggests, slaves
could be viewed as property and treated as one pleased. This is no longer
the case. Similarly, he argues, in the past land could be treated how
we pleased, and viewed entirely under the aegis of economics. Now, however,
Leopold argues, it is time to consider our ethical relationship with the
land. He goes on to maintain that what is needed is a new ethic which
'enlarges the boundaries of the community to include soils, waters, plants,
and animals, or collectively, the land'. His guiding principle is famously
expressed: 'A thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity,
stability and beauty of the biotic community. It is wrong when it tends
otherwise'.
Straightforward though these pages of Leopold's writing may seem, they
are in practice anything but. In part, this is due to the unsystematic
nature of his writing: he has, as it were, set a number of hares running,
but never catches any of them. It is these complications that underpin
a number of debates in recent holistic environmental ethics.
Exercise:
Consider the following themes and issues in your own
reading:
- How does Leopold envisage the place of individuals
in his land ethic? He presents it as a principle of ethical extension:
human ethics are extended to include the land; the land ethic does not
replace human ethics. But what happens where human ethics and the land
ethic come into conflict - in the case of high population growth, for
instance?
- What exactly does he mean by saying that humans
are "plain members and citizens" "only a member of a
biotic team?" Is he suggesting that it's inappropriate for humans
to manage land, for instance?
- This issue is exacerbated by looking at the different
models Leopold uses to describe the land. Sometimes he calls it a "fountain
of energy"; sometimes a "community" and sometimes an
"organism". But these models present quite different pictures
of land and human relationships with it. For instance, if "the
land" is an organism, are humans then just organs? What might the
implications of this be?
- Leopold several times uses the language of "biotic
right" in the context of species he views as key to the survival
of ecosystems. But what exactly does he mean by "right" here?
- Leopold raises the idea of land health. This has
proved one of the most controversial areas of holistic environmental
ethics, as we shall see. Think about what "land health" might
mean, and how one might go about making sense of it.
- What are "integrity, stability and beauty"?
How can they be measured? Are they appropriate criteria for assessing
ecological right and wrong?
Interpreting Leopold
The interpretation of Leopold has recently become controversial in environmental
ethics. J Baird Callicott, whose work we shall shortly be considering,
championed Leopold's writing in the 1980s, publishing a collection of
essays called Companion to a Sand County Almanac (Wisconsin: University
of Wisconsin Press 1987). These essays interpret Leopold as adopting a
holistic, non- anthropocentric approach. But more recently Bryan Norton
(1996) in his essay "The Constancy of Leopold's Land Ethic"
(in Light and Katz (eds.) Environmental Pragmatism (London: Routledge)
p. 84-102 argues that whilst Leopold did consider the biotic community
to be a organism, he also considered that humans "must and should"
manage it; and that ultimately, as parts of the biotic organism, human
and biotic interests would coincide.
Whatever one thinks about these different interpretations, Leopold's
stress on the integrity, stability and beauty of the biotic community
contrasts strikingly with the individualists we looked at in Block 2.
First, the community as a whole, rather than the individual, is the focus
of moral significance; it is viewed as valuable in itself, not just as
a collection of valuable individuals. Secondly, ecological qualities such
as integrity and stability are of primary value. Such qualities cannot
be valued in individualist approaches where individual living organisms
or their experiences are the whole locus of value.
It is this contrast of holistic with individualist environmental ethics
which has led to some of the most controversial publications in environmental
ethics - sometimes called the animal liberation/environmental ethics debate
(a title adopted for a useful collection of essays on the subject edited
by Eugene Hargrove).
Web Resources
One useful resource, with tributes to Leopold, are The Wilderness Society's
pages:
On the Land Ethic (note the links to further pages in the right hand
column of the first page)
Also useful is the website of The Aldo
Leopold Foundation which includes discussion about applying the land
ethic today.
The Animal Liberation/Environmental Ethics Debate
This debate was kick-started with the publication in 1980 of J. Baird
Callicott's paper 'Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair' (originally
published in vol 2 of the journal Environmental Ethics, but subsequently
reprinted in a number of environmental ethics collections.)
Callicott begins his article by discussing the way in which the animal
liberation debate had been set up in the 1970s. He suggests that it had
been seen as a debate with two sides: between those who argue that animals
lack particular qualities (eg language, rationality, sentience, self-awareness
etc) and thus moral standing; and those who argue that animals do have
these qualities, and therefore do have moral standing. Callicott characterises
this as a debate between moral humanism and humane moralism. But Callicott
wants to suggest there's a third position, the land ethic derived from
Leopold's writing, which emphasises the importance of the biotic community.
And, he maintains, this position is seriously in tension with animal liberation.
Callicott characterises the land ethic as maintaining that the ecological
whole is the ultimate measure of moral value. Indeed, the primary human
duty is protection of the biotic community or organism as a whole, even
where this means considerable human sacrifice. The value of individual
organisms lies in their ecological function; and so the well-being of
individual organisms should be considered inasmuch as they contribute
to the ecological whole. Thus the value of individuals is context dependent,
relating to their function and significance in the whole. If they are
vital to the ecosystem - members of what are sometimes called "keystone"
species - then they are of very high value. If they are not significant
to the system, or they are very common, or their role can easily be performed
by another organism, or there are too many of them, then their value is
much diminished. This implies, for instance, that the value of an individual
varies in relation to how many others there are, what it does, and so
on.
Thus, the value of rare/functionally vital parts/members can trump the
value of common/functionally redundant parts. In the interests of biodiversity,
it is more important to protect an individual of an endangered species
than an individual of a common species, even if the individual of the
endangered species is not sentient, and the individual of the common species
is. So, for instance, when the growth in the hungry non-native rabbit
population in Western Australia threatens the existence of a rare native
Australian wild grass species, the rabbits should be killed to protect
the grass. Even where endangered species are not involved, if large numbers
of one species (eg deer) are threatening the stability of the ecological
community as a whole, then hunting may be required. This remains so even
if hunting involves suffering as well as killing. The most essential species
(such as the pollinating honey bee) are more important than, for instance,
higher mammals which play a far less vital role in the biological community.
This clearly reflects on human beings, who are not only not vital to the
system, but who actually destroy it. Indeed, Callicott suggested that
the more misanthropy there is in an ethical system, the more ecological
it is, and that the human population should be, in total, about twice
that of bears!
The land ethic also suggests that moral consideration should be given
to (some) plants. The ecological community is dependent on plants, insects
etc for its flourishing; so they must be taken into account in moral decision-making
even where this means hardship/suffering for sentient animals. Obviously
this is not true of all plants (not, for instance for alien species which
are not important to, or even harmful to the ecosystem). This directly
clashes with (for instance) both Singer's and Regan's basis for moral
considerability, since neither would understand plants to be sentient
nor subject-of-a-life.
These reflections on the land ethic led Callicott into further doubt
about ethical individualism in the form of animal liberation. A land ethic,
he maintained, recognises the importance of predator/prey relationships,
and acknowledges - even celebrates - death, suffering, disease and decay.
These are part of the food chain and that which keeps life going. Animal
liberationists and utilitarians in general regard pain as the worst bad
possible. But pain is essential to the ecological system which could not
operate without it. Denial of ecological embodiment (eg discomfort with
predation), Callicott argued, denies evolutionary and ethical continuity.
Weighing into animal liberation even more, Callicott argues that the
idea of "liberating" domesticated animals is an absurd one anyway.
Domesticated animals are human creations - and ecological disasters. Singer's
parallel with the liberation of slaves/women etc completely breaks down.
Most domestic animals, being unable to survive on their own, would die
if liberated. Their species would become extinct. Others might go feral,
compete with wildlife and possibly eliminate it, which would be ecologically
disastrous.
It is views such as these which led to a rift developing between holistic
environmental ethics and the individualistic positions of animal liberationists.
Some Individualist Responses to Holism in Environmental Ethics
Unsurprisingly, some fairly heated responses to papers such as Callicott's
have emerged from individualists, most particularly from Tom Regan. These
fall into two broad (but linked) categories:
- Defending the individual
- Attacking the idea of holism
1. Defending the individual
Tom Regan in the Case for Animal Rights p. 359-363 famously describes
approaches like those of Callicott and Sagoff as environmental fascism.
He uses this label because one interpretation of fascism is of a political
philosophy willing to sacrifice the individual for the needs of the whole.
The land ethic, Regan claims, is an ecological version of this. Furthermore,
Regan suggests, presumably these writers intend human beings to be seen
as part of the land community or land organism. Separating them off would
seem very peculiar for a position which claimed to be ecocentric. But
if humans are included in the land community, does this mean that they
can be sacrificed for the good of the ecosystem? Can you, Regan asks,
allow the good of the community to outweigh an individual's rights? This
implies that holistic ethicists would sacrifice a human life for a rare
wildflower! Regan argues that the "rights view cannot abide"
ecological holism as it draws conclusions so radically opposed to the
right to life of those who are subjects-of-a-life, and, further suggests
the protection of organisms and non-living things who are not rights-bearers.
2. Attacking holism
A whole range of further questions, which we shall look at briefly in
this module, and which will be considered in more depth in the module
Land as Community, concern whether an ecosystem (and even more so, a species)
can be thought of as 'a whole' at all. Critics have argued that ecosystems
cannot be said to have 'better' or 'worse' states, that it is impossible
to identify criteria of land health; that qualities such as 'diversity'
'stability' or 'integrity' cannot be fixed on as 'good states' for ecosystems.
Ecosystems are constantly in a state of change; it isn't clear what is
better or worse for them. But without being able to identify a good state
for them, how can it be clear what behaviour towards them is ethical or
not, nor when it is appropriate to sacrifice individuals in their interests?
Are ecosystems the kinds of thing which can have interests at all?
Ecosystems writ large: the Gaia hypothesis
While most of the work in holistic environmental ethics has focused on
ecosystems the 'Gaia hypothesis', and the host of metaphysical and ethical
questions raised by it, concerns the entire Earth. The 'Gaia hypothesis'
originated in the work of scientist James Lovelock in his book Gaia:
a new look at life on Earth (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1979)
and The Ages of Gaia (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1982). But perhaps
the most concise summary of Lovelock's hypothesis is, found in his paper
"Geophysiology - the Science of Gaia" which he presented to
the annual conference of the American Geophysical Union in 1988. Here
he describes 'Gaia theory' as:
"about the evolution of a tightly coupled system whose constituents
are the biota and their material environment, which comprises the atmosphere,
the oceans and the surface rocks. Self-regulation of important properties
such as climate and chemical composition, is seen as a consequence of
this evolutionary process."
So the basis of Lovelock's scientific contention is that the Earth, as
a whole, can be described as a living system. The evolution of biological
life is coupled inseparably with the evolution of the physical surface
of the earth and the chemical composition of the atmosphere. The so-called
'inanimate' parts of the Earth, he argues, are like the bark of a tree
or the shell of a snail: an essential part of a living system. Lovelock
argues that life on Earth shapes its environment, both the atmosphere
and its physical surroundings, in order to maintain conditions comfortable
for the continuance of life. The atmosphere and temperature of the Earth
are kept, by the living organisms on it, as near to a constant, or in
biological terms, to homeostasis, as possible. Where there are external
threats to this homeostasis - such as by the impact of huge asteroids
which are frequently cited as the cause for several mass extinctions in
the history of the planet - living organisms respond by a series of what
Lovelock calls 'feedback mechanisms'. As an example of such a mechanism
at work, Lovelock points out that since the Proterozoic period, between
1 and 2 billion years ago, the sun has become at least 30% and perhaps
50% hotter. Yet the temperature on Earth has remained relatively constant,
and continued to support life. Lovelock contends that the relative constancy
of the Earth's temperature is caused by feedback mechanisms operated by
Earth's living organisms.
To illustrate this, Lovelock created, in The Ages of Gaia a computer
model which he entitles 'Daisyworld'. In its simplest form, Daisyworld
is a planet rather like ours, but which has alive on its surface only
black and white daisies. Lovelock assumes that these daisies can survive
only between temperatures of 5 and 40o C. Below this temperature range,
it is too cold for daisies to grow; above it, the climate is too hot.
As in our solar system, over millions of years, the heat of the sun slowly
intensifies. Initially, when the sun is cooler, black daisies predominate.
Being black, they can absorb the sun's heat, and not only keep themselves
alive, but retain the overall temperature of the planet at a level above
5C. As the sun gets hotter, however, white daisies, by the process of
natural selection, become increasingly common. With their ability to reflect
sunlight, they can keep both themselves, and the surface of the planet
cooler and at a relatively constant temperature. There will still, of
course, come a point where the sun's heat is such that, even with the
entire planet covered in white daisies, their reflectivity is not enough
to keep the planet viable for life. At this point, the feedback mechanisms
cease to function, and Daisyworld becomes a deserted, barren planet. The
effect of the living organisms however, purely by natural selection, has
been to keep the temperature of the planet between 5 and 40C for a much
longer period than would have occurred on a barren planet, which would
have been colder initially and passed 40C much sooner.
Although the Earth is, of course, far more complex than Daisyworld, Lovelock
contends that similar feedback mechanisms occur. Climate is regulated
not only by the reflectivity of the land surface and of clouds, but also
by the composition of the atmosphere - an increase in carbon dioxide,
for instance, warming the earth by the so-called 'greenhouse effect'.
Similar feedback mechanisms act to keep the sea at constant rather than
increasing salinity, and oxygen at 21% of the atmosphere, a level high
enough for fires (all important in forest ecology) to occur, but not so
high that any flame would kindle continental conflagration. For millions
of years the Earth has thus responded to external changes such as asteroid
impact and increased solar heat by evolutionary processes involving the
evolution not only of species but also of their environments.
In this sense, Lovelock contends that the Earth behaves like a single
living organism, in that the flora and fauna on Earth act together to
regulate the climate and temperature of Earth in order to produce the
best conditions for life. (Usually, Lovelock uses the term "organism"
metaphorically, but sometimes he writes as if he thinks the earth is actually
an organism). Lovelock argues that this regulation of the Earth is not
a teleological, or purposive process, and dismisses all suggestions that
Gaia might be conscious or have a deliberate aim - something which he
argues is borne out by the model of Daisyworld. Thus Lovelock, ostensibly
at least, has not himself developed 'Gaia' into a thoroughgoing metaphysical
or ethical system, (although periodically, he uses language which suggests
this). However, there is no doubt that the Gaia hypothesis can have important
ethical implications, although these are dependent on the interpretation
of Lovelock's hypothesis which is adopted.
Lovelock himself argues that the Earth is not fragile, and that it has
survived many potential crises in the past by adapting to changed conditions.
This may mean that the Earth moves to new equilibria, but that life still
continues. He suggests that the Earth may have 'vital organs' which, while
possibly essential for life on Earth to survive at all, are certainly
essential for the Earth to continue at its current equilibrium. These
vital organs, he suggests, may be the tropical rainforests, deep sea algae
and prokaryotic bacteria. Their destruction could mean that Gaia moves
to a new equilibrium; an equilibrium which may support some kind of life,
but which would not support human life. With this background, the ethical
implications of Gaia are not focused around protecting Gaia herself (she
is well able to tend for herself!) but rather on the preservation of human
beings from the devastating consequences of a new equilibrium. Therefore,
actions that might force Gaia to a new equilibrium - such as global warming
by an increase in atmospheric CO2 - should be avoided since it may ultimately
lead to the destruction of human beings. This provides an anthropocentric
reason for the protection of Gaia, and could support the development of
a holistic anthropocentric environmental ethic.
Other groups have, however, developed different ethical conclusions,
loosely based on the Gaia hypothesis. These highlight the living organismic
nature of the Earth, and, in contrast with Lovelock, stress its fragility.
This can result in holistic ethical stances where the 'wellbeing of the
planet' is put before the wellbeing of individual human beings. More radical
versions of these views argue that a reduction in human population is
an ethical necessity. Such plural ethical interpretations make clear the
ambiguous position which Lovelock's hypothesis may hold in environmental
ethics.
Reconciling Positions
The preceding sections have described a range of different, and sometimes
conflicting, positions adopted by those working in environmental ethics
- in particular there seems to be a rift between the individualism of
animal liberation positions in contrast with the holism of some environmental
ethics. (It should be remembered, however, that there are individualist
environmental ethical positions and that animals are still morally relevant
to holistic environmental ethics). Several strategies are possible to
deal with these concerns. One is just to, as it were, bite the bullet,
and maintain either that only individuals or only ecological wholes are
of moral significance. We have already looked at a number of philosophers
who adopt this view. A second is to develop an approach to environmental
ethics which takes both individual and holistic concerns into account
in one form or another. A third is to adopt some form of moral pluralism,
which I will explain further shortly.
One central environmental philosopher who allows for both individualist
and holistic values is Holmes Rolston whose views are laid out in his
systematic work Environmental Ethics: Duties to and Values in the
Natural World (Philadelphia: Temple University Press 1988).
Rolston argues that there is objective value in the natural world, both
in individuals and in systems. The baseline of individual value is the
telos of each individual organism. Every organism has a good of its own,
and is thus a holder of value, even if not a beholder of it. To this extent,
Rolston's views are not dissimilar to those of Taylor. However, Rolston
contends that different characteristics - such as sentience or ability
for conscious reflection - add value, so that the more sophisticated a
living organism, the more valuable it is. Alongside this individualist
approach, Rolston also develops an understanding of intrinsic value applicable
to ecosystems and species. Species, he argues, provide the normative genetic
'set' for the individual, and this genetic set is as evidently the property
of the species as of the individual through whom it passes. A species
is a form of life that defends itself and, according to Rolston, thus
has value. The ecosystem, and indeed the biosphere as a whole, is a life-creating
process. Ethical attention should be not focused on an ecosystem as an
individual, but rather as an interconnected matrix within which life evolved
and continues to develop. As the womb of life, both producing and nurturing
it, the ecosystem is an appropriate unit for moral concern. It would be
bizarre, Rolston insists, to value the organisms, the products of the
system, without valuing the process which produced them. This wild, systemic
value is entirely separate from human culture, exists independently of
humans and is increasingly threatened by human development.
In developing a complex system of this kind, Rolston tries to take account
of all the different kinds of concerns which might make up environmental
ethics. Other environmental philosophers have concluded that, given the
diversity of possible objects of moral concern (sentient animals, living
organisms, ecosystems, species, the Earth, biodiversity etc.) and so many
different approaches to environmental ethics (rights-theories, utilitarianism,
virtues theories and so on) it is a mistake to attempt to capture these
within some monistic ethical theory. A series of debates in the environmental
ethics journals about "moral pluralism" followed in the 1990s.
Some of this material is collected in Light and Rolston Part IV.
Exercise:
To complete this section consider again the issues raised
this week. Which would you say you found to be the most important, and
why?
Send a note to the discussion site expressing some of
your thoughts on this theme.
Modified version of notes by Clare Palmer
|