Introduction
Many environmental (and animal) ethicists have wanted to develop approaches
to ethics which take animals and/or the non-human natural world directly
into account in ethical decision-making. Such approaches are alien to
many traditional forms of ethical decision making, where animals and/or
the environment have been of only indirect ethical concern. Kant, for
instance, thought that cruelty towards animals was unethical. But this
was not because of the harm it caused animals, but rather because the
committing of such harm would 'brutalise' humans and make them more likely
subsequently to harm other people. For Kant, animals are of indirect ethical
concern - it is only other humans who are of direct ethical concern.
However, as Routley's Last Man example suggests, by the 1970s, philosophers
were trying to develop ways of extending traditional ethical approaches
to take account of the new questions raised by environmental and animal
issues. Many different kinds of revisions and extensions have been proposed.
This block looks at a number of these, united by their "individualist"
approach.
Mapping Individualism in Environmental Ethics: An Overview
Traditional Ethics
Almost all mainstream ethical approaches focus on the value of individual
human beings or individual human experiences in one way or another. Utilitarianism,
for instance, focuses on either minimizing the pains and maximizing the
pleasures of individuals or on satisfying their preferences. Kantianism
emphasizes the priceless worth of the individual and how individuals should
be treated not merely as means but as ends in themselves. The language
of debate about ethics in political philosophy centres on the notion of
the rights of the individual.
It is not surprising, then, that one of the most widespread moves in environmental
and animal ethics is to attempt to extend these ethical frameworks centred
on human individuals to include non-human individuals as well. The obvious
point of attack here is to ask what it is about an individual human being
that makes him or her valuable in the terms of the ethical framework being
considered. Another way of putting this is to ask the question "What
is it which makes humans morally considerable here?" ('Morally considerable'
is a shorthand expression for 'someone or something who counts morally').
Depending on the answer to that question, it might be argued in response
that the criterion for moral considerability being used is in some sense
problematic - in particular that it cannot exclude some or all non-humans
whilst including all humans. We will look at this move further when looking
at the specific instances later.
In this block I am going to look at some of the most important accounts
of environmental/animal ethics which fall into this "individualistic"
category. They have been developed from a variety of different traditional
approaches. In thinking about these positions, it's helpful to consider
them along three different axes. These are:
- Consequentialist/Deontological
- Sentience-centred/Life centred
- Egalitarian/hierarchical
1. Consequentialist/Deontological
Some of the individualist positions we will be considering here are consequentialist,
and some deontological. Consequentialist approaches are more or less closely
outgrowths of utilitarianism, whilst deontological accounts tend to draw
on Kant and theories of rights.
2. Sentience-centred/Life centred
Although this is something of a generalization, individualist positions
tend to fall into two categories. The first focuses on sentience (the
ability to feel pain and pleasure) and other associated "higher-order"
abilities including consciousness. These positions generally only extend
moral considerability to animals, and possibly only some animals. The
second focuses on life - being alive means an organism meets the necessary
and sufficient criteria to qualify for direct moral considerability.
3. Egalitarian/Hierarchical
For some individualist positions, any organism which meets the criterion
of moral considerability is as morally significant as any other. In Bentham's
words: everyone counts for one and no-one for more than one. In an egalitarian
ethical system, just to count gives you the same standing as everyone
else. Other ethical systems, though, are hierarchical. There is a baseline
to be met to count at all. (For instance, you must be alive to count).
But there are other criteria in the system which mean that you count more
- you can get a kind of "value-added" if you like. For instance,
you might be morally considerable just by being alive. But you might get
extra "value-added" - be worth more - if you are sentient and
intelligent. In such a case, having to choose between killing an insect
and killing a dog would be straightforward - the dog is worth more. This
contrasts with an egalitarian ethical system - where all living things
count for the same, it would be just as bad to kill an insect as a dog.
It's these three axes which lie at the heart of the differences between
the different individualist approaches to environmental ethics we'll be
considering here. This can by no means be a comprehensive survey, but
it will at least outline some of the main proposed positions.
Singer's Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism is the ethical tradition that lends itself most obviously
to the sort of extension of traditional ethical approaches considered
above. Even in its earliest form, its founder Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832)
thought utilitarianism should take animals into account. In his Introduction
to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789) he wrote:
It may one day be recognised that the number of the legs, the villosity
of the skin or the termination of the os sacrum are reasons equally
insufficient for abandoning a sensitive being to the same fate. What
else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty
of reason, or perhaps the faculty of discourse? But a full grown horse
or dog is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversible
animal than an infant of a day or a week or even a month old. But suppose
they were otherwise, what would it avail? The question is not, Can they
reason? nor Can they talk? but Can they suffer?
This understanding of utilitarianism as including animals was largely
neglected until 1975, when the utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer published
his book Animal Liberation. This book is now viewed as one of the key
works in the animal liberation and environmental movements. What is significant
about Singer's arguments for the development of environmental ethics is
that organisms other than humans are directly taken into account in moral
decision-making. They are not being valued as resources, for their usefulness
to human beings, but rather they are being taken into account for what
they are in themselves - in ways which may cause inconvenience or even
difficulty for human beings.
In Animal Liberation, Singer adopts the classic utilitarian view that
the ultimate good is to minimise pain and maximise pleasure (in fact,
he focuses on the former of these). He argues that since animals as well
as humans can feel pain, a case can be made for equality between humans
and animals. That is to say, he argues, that animals should be taken into
moral consideration equally with humans where the infliction of suffering
is involved, because animals, like humans are sentient. For Singer, the
capacity for suffering is "the prerequisite for having interests
at all" - that is to say, it's the prerequisite for being morally
considerable. Since animals can feel pain, they have an interest in avoiding
it; and he argues that the principle of equal consideration requires that
animal interests in not suffering be taken equally into account with human
interests in not suffering. We can already see here where Singer fits
along the three axes discussed above:
- He's a utilitarian and as such a consequentialist;
- He's sentience-centred rather than life-centred;
- He's egalitarian rather than hierarchical (although as I shall point
out, he shifts a bit on this in his later work).
Singer argues that failure to take sentient animals into equal moral
consideration with humans is speciesism. This term is something of a slippery
one, and is defined in different ways by different people. One definition
of it is something like the position that "humans are morally entitled
to prefer the interests of fellow humans over equivalent interests of
other animals". Singer maintains that speciesism follows an identical
pattern to racism and sexism - and is equally to be condemned. He maintains:
"pain and suffering are bad and should be minimised irrespective
of the race, sex or species of the being that suffers." However,
he does note that the same amount of physical pain can cause more total
human suffering than animal suffering. This is because humans have capacities
of memory and anticipation of pain which animals may not have; because
of the depth of emotional ties between humans which may mean the suffering
of one has a negative effect on others; and because certain kinds of suffering
may upset whole human communities in ways which wouldn't happen amongst
animals. Of course, Singer points out, there are some situations in which
this may not be the case - where for instance humans can gain some relief
from suffering by knowing it will shortly end, in ways which animals cannot.
Now read Singer's 'All
Animals are Equal' (this is a very early piece by Singer).
Exercise
When reading this article, think carefully about the
following issues:
- Singer lines up animal liberation alongside the
movements for racial and sexual equality; and speciesism alongside racism
and sexism. But is speciesism really like racism or sexism? (Are they
like one another?) In thinking about this you may want to consider Singer's
characterisation of these movements, and whether this is how they would
more generally be characterised.
- What does Singer mean by "moral equality"
and "factual equality"? How important do you think his distinction
here is?
- Singer raises the issue of vivisection and suggests
that, in terms of suffering, experimenting on a human baby is much the
same as experimenting on other adult mammals. What do you think he is
doing in making this comparison (suggesting that vivisection should
be extended to babies, or rejecting it?) What do you think of the method
Singer uses in making this point?
- Have a go at summarising the "flow" of
Singer's argument - how his main points follow from one another. With
which claims (if any) do you part company from him? Are there places
where you think his argument is flawed?
Answer all these questions in your own notes and send the result of at
least one of them to the discussion site.
Singer's Later Work
Singer's Animal Liberation is often thought to have given birth to the
modern animal liberation movement as we know it. But a number of nagging
questions were raised by critics about the book, to which Singer has attempted
to respond. Since philosophically interesting points are raised, we will
briefly consider them here.
A number of critics pointed out that Singer's position might work quite
well to prevent animals from suffering. But it didn't work well to prevent
them from being killed, provided they were killed painlessly and a new
animal bred in their place. This follows from the nature of the kind of
utilitarianism Singer adopted. If what matters is maximising happiness
and minimising pain, so long as no pain is caused, and a new animal at
least as happy as one killed is produced, nothing has been lost by killing.
Thus animals become, in essence, replaceable. Singer wasn't very happy
with this, and so in his more recent writing attempted to develop a form
of utilitarianism which would overcome this problem. He adopted a different
form of utilitarianism - preference utilitarianism - to refine his earlier
position. What does this mean?
Well, there are two popular forms of utilitarianism - classical utilitarianism
which focuses on pleasure and pain, and preference utilitarianism which
focuses on satisfying preferences. By adding a layer of preference utilitarianism
onto his position, Singer tried get round the painless killing and replaceability
problem. He continued to maintain that the baseline of moral considerability
was sentience. Any sentient being must be taken into account in ethical
decision-making. But there is also a class of beings who are capable of
having preferences, which requires a level of intelligence and consciousness,
not just sentience. And those beings who have preferences will (generally
speaking) have preferences to go on living, rather than being killed.
A preference utilitarian should try to satisfy those preferences by not
killing, whether or not the killing would be painless. In this way, Singer
creates a class of preference-havers who receive a level of protection
from killing not available to the sentient non preference-havers. In other
words, he moves away from an egalitarian position towards a hierarchy
which has three tiers - one which looks something like this:
Singer's later three-tier position
Top Tier
The Personally Morally Considerable
(Most adult humans, apes, dolphins etc)
Self conscious
Irreplaceable
Persons________________________________
Middle Tier
The Impersonally Morally Considerable
(animals and humans which lack self-consciousness - incl. foetuses and
infants)
Replaceable
______________________________________
Bottom Tier
The Morally Inconsiderable
(Rocks, rivers, insects, plants, molluscs)
Sentience still marks the line between being morally considerable
or not. Rocks, rivers, insects etc which can't - according to Singer -
feel pain, don't count at all; they fall into the bottom tier. Animals
which are sentient but not conscious fall into the middle tier; they may
be painlessly killed and replaced without anything unethical having transpired
(Singer uses a chicken as an example in this category). Then animals in
the top tier - such as humans, dolphins, primates - who have preferences
to go on living may not (generally speaking) be killed ethically, however
painless this might be. (Singer is not, unfortunately, very clear about
into which tier the most widely eaten animals like cows and pigs fall).
Picture: some members of a top tier species contemplating
the inconsiderable
Question for Thought:
What do you think is the main objection
which might be raised to Singer's preference utilitarianism here? If you
are foxed, have a look at the article by Michael Lockwood in the reading
tip below.
Reading Tip: Singer develops his philosophical approach towards
animals, as mentioned above, in a number of later writings. Most useful
amongst these is the section on animals in his book Practical Ethics (of
which there are numerous editions, the more recent the better) and his
1979 article "Killing Humans and Killing Animals" in Inquiry
22 145-156. This edition of Inquiry has a number of interesting articles,
including an attack on Singer by Michael Lockwood in "Killing and
the Preference for Life" Inquiry 22 p.157-170.
Web Resource
There's a huge amount about Peter Singer on the web - his controversial
views about abortion and euthanasia as well as animals have cause uproar
in various quarters. Some websites you might like to look at:
An interview with Singer in Reason magazine
http://www.reason.com/0012/rb.the.html
And finally a site with masses of links to Singer's writings and writing
about him:
http://www.petersingerlinks.com
Animals and Rights
"Animal rights" is an expression most commonly used in a broad
sense to cover a wide range of ethical positions where animals are directly
morally considerable. In a philosophical rather than a popular sense,
however, the expression "animal rights" should be confined to
philosophical positions which actively adopt the language of rights. The
most important of these positions has been developed by Tom Regan, whose
book The Case for Animal Rights was published in 1984. Regan adapts key
ideas from Kantian ethical theory and incorporates them into an extended
rights theory which includes animals alongside humans.
Regan's argument is complicated and it is impossible to reproduce more
than a summary here. However, we can look at some of the basic steps in
his argument.
First, there is a descriptive step - where Regan talks about the kind
of beings he thinks animals are. It's important to note that Regan confines
his argument about animal rights to adult mammals. These animals, he argue,
should be seen as conscious, and as the kind of organisms which have beliefs
and desires. (These claims in themselves put him at odds with many modern
- and less modern - philosophers.) They have a degree of self-awareness,
and can act with intention. And, he says, they have "preference autonomy"
- they have independent preferences and the ability to act on them. Their
lives can go well for them, if they can ":
- pursue and obtain what they prefer,
- they take satisfaction in pursuing and obtaining what they prefer
and
- what they obtain and prefer is in their interests." (p.117).
It follows from this, Regan says, that animals can also be harmed - by
having unwanted things inflicted upon them (like pain) or by being deprived
of things (including their lives - but this is quite a complicated argument,
and to pursue this you will need to look at Regan's book itself.)
After this descriptive step, Regan makes his prescriptive step. He first
argues for a deontological position against a consequentialist one. For
Regan, it is not the consequences of an action which determine whether
it is right or wrong, but whether it conforms to a duty. And Regan is
a rights theorist; so for him our primary duties are to respect the rights
of individuals - irrespective of the consequences.
Then Regan makes a key distinction - that between moral agents and moral
patients. Moral agents are those who are able to act morally, that is
to behave in a moral way. Only humans as far as we know are able to do
this - and importantly, only some humans, generally speaking normal adults,
but not children, babies, or those with some kinds of mental disability.
Moral patients on the other hand are not able to make moral decisions,
and are not accountable for what they do morally. But nonetheless, Regan
argues, these beings are still morally considerable. We don't say, for
instance, that we don't have to take children into account when making
moral decisions just because they aren't capable of making them themselves!
And similarly, he is going to argue, even though animals are not moral
agents, they are moral patients.
On what basis? Here, Regan returns to his earlier description of what
animals are like, and coins the expression "subject-of-a-life".
What does he mean by this? He says:
"Individuals are subject-of-a-life if they have beliefs and desires;
perception, memory and a sense of the future, including their own future;
an emotional life together with feelings of pleasure and pain; preference
and welfare interests; a psychophysical unity over time and an individual
welfare in the sense that their experiential life fares well or ill
for them….Those who satisfy the subject-of-a-life criterion themselves
have a distinctive kind of value - intrinsic value…" (The
Case for Animal Rights p.244).
It is on this basis - of the intrinsic value of beings that are subject-of-a-life
- that Regan maintains there are rights. All animals (including humans)
which are subject of a life have rights. By this, Regan means that they
can make valid claims to be treated respectfully - even if they are not
able to make those claims on their own behalf. And these rights, according
to Regan, are natural rights. They are not rights contractually agreed
upon, or voluntarily given by humans to other humans and animals. The
rights exist because of the very nature of being subject-of-a-life. And
all rights-holders should be treated respectfully - not harmed, not killed,
and protected from those who would harm them or kill them. Indeed, Regan
here adopts a version of the Kantian principle that people should never
be treated merely as means to an end, but as ends in themselves. And he
applies this to all rights holders - which means all adult mammals. They
should all be treated as ends, never merely as means.
Where does this place Regan on our three axes?
- He's clearly a deontologist, not a consequentialist - much of his
book is aimed at showing why Singer's consequentialist arguments are
mistaken.
- He's sentience-centred (broadly speaking - though he has even more
stringent criteria than just sentience) rather than life-centred
- He's an egalitarian. Although his sphere of moral considerability
is fairly limited (that is, to adult mammals) everyone in it is worth
the same.
Some further aspects of Regan's views can be explored in the reading.
Second reading: Tom Regan: "Animal Rights, Human Wrongs" in
Zimmermann pp. 41-55 This is an article-length version of Regan's views,
which he published in the journal Environmental Ethics in 1980.
Exercise:
Think about the following questions when you read:
- Is Regan's understanding of cruelty an appropriate
one? Can you think of cases which you might want to call cruelty which
would not fit under his description?
- What are Regan's key points of attack on utilitarianism?
List them out one by one, then see whether you think they stand up to
scrutiny.
- Regan introduces the concept of inherent value as
a way into explaining why one might attribute rights.
a) What does he claim to be the grounds for this inherent value?
b) Is it actually a clearer idea than the rights he is trying to explain
by using it?
- Does Regan establish a convincing case for animal
rights?
- Regan is interested in establishing that animals
have moral rights here. He doesn't address the question of legal rights.
How do you think they might be related? Do you think he might want his
moral position to be made a legal requirement?
As before make sure you attempt an answer to all of these questions and
send one that you are pleased with or on that you think there is a problem
with to the discussion site.
Web Resource
An article on philosophical approaches to animals by Dave Eaton (a former
MAVE student)
http://www.animalaid.org.uk/campaign/pride/eaton.htm
Another summary of Regan:
http://www.thevegetariansite.com/ethics_regan.htm
Review of Regan's latest book Defending Animal Rights
http://www.cultureandanimals.org/book.htm
Extending Value Further: Valuing all living organisms
For many environmental ethicists, though, positions like Singer's and
Regan's do not go far enough. They argue that for both philosophers, the
environment is still a 'backdrop' to those organisms which can feel pleasure
and pain or are intelligent "subjects-of-a-life". Other organisms
are still only valued as long as they are useful. Furthermore, some argue,
what is going on here is a valuing of things which are nearly, but not
quite, human. Organisms with human-like characteristics, on this account,
are valuable; those which are not, are not. And since value is assessed
on how like humans an organism is (how intelligent, how conscious, how
sentient), non-humans will always fall short, always be seen as like a
human but lacking the full value of humanity. To some thinkers, this is
not an adequate approach to environmental ethics; it fails to recognise
that a being may be unlike humans and yet still valuable. John Rodman
captured this by saying:
Is this, then, the new enlightenment - to see nonhuman animals as
imbeciles, wilderness as a human vegetable?... It is perhaps analogous
to seeing women as defective men who lack penises, or humans as defective
sea mammals who lack sonar capacity… (Rodman, John (1977) 'The
Liberation of Nature' Inquiry 20 83-145)
It was partly out of such concerns that life-centred (sometimes called
biocentric) environmental ethics developed. According to this view it
is being alive, rather than being sentient (or conscious, or having beliefs
and desires) which confers moral considerability upon an organism. Of
course, this view is not an entirely new one. A form of it exists within
the philosophy of Jainism. And Albert Schweitzer, in his 1933 book Philosophy
and Civilisation, developed a principle of reverence for life, based on
his view that every organism has a "will-to-live". This fascinating
early account is clearly a forerunner to later biocentric positions in
environmental ethics.
However, it was not until the late 1970s that a more rigorous attempt
to defend such an approach to environmental ethics was developed by Kenneth
Goodpaster. His article constitutes the third reading in this block.
Reading 3: Kenneth Goodpaster: 'On Being Morally Considerable'
This paper was first published in 1978 in the Journal of Philosophy 75
308-325 and has been reprinted subsequently in a number of different collections.
This witnesses to its importance as the foundation for many modern individualist
positions in environmental ethics. Goodpaster considers the question 'what
makes something morally considerable?' in some detail, arguing that 'X's
being a living thing is both necessary and sufficient for moral considerability
so understood'. This is quite a complex paper, so you will need to read
it slowly and think through the argument Goodpaster is making.
Clarifying Goodpaster's Argument:
Check that you can answer the following questions about Goodpaster's account:
- Why does Goodpaster prefer to talk about moral considerability rather
than rights?
- What is the distinction he makes between moral considerability and
moral significance?
- How does he distinguish between questions of intelligibility and questions
of normative substance?
- Why does Goodpaster maintain that sentience alone is a sufficient
but not a necessary condition for moral considerability?
- On what arguments does Goodpaster primarily base his case that plants
are morally considerable?
Notes on Interests
It's useful here to be distinguish between two different ways in which
we think of the word "interest". We sometimes use the word to
mean something that actively engages us: we are interested in something,
we "take an interest". This is sometimes called a "preference
interest". And on other occasions, we use the word to mean something
which is good for us, "in our interests". This is sometimes
called a "welfare interest". Clearly, we can take an interest
in something which is not in our interests (smoking, for instance). Goodpaster
is using the distinction in a slightly different way. He's suggesting
that an organism which lacks the psychological wherewithal to take an
interest in anything (no preference interests) still has things which
are in its interests (welfare interests). For instance, my pot-plants
don't take any interest in being watered. But it's in their interests
that I do so (welfare interests). Goodpaster is suggesting that in terms
of moral considerability, it is welfare interests that matter. Plants,
and other non-sentient organisms, have a wellbeing.
They can be in better or worse states. They can be healthy or unhealthy,
flourishing or not flourishing. It is in their interests to flourish,
even if they can't take an interest in it
Objections to Goodpaster
1) Singer commented scathingly on this article:
All we mean when we say it is in the interests of a tree to be watered
is that the tree needs water if it is to continue to live and grow normally;
if we regard this as evidence that the tree has interests we may as
well say that it is in the interests of a car to be lubricated regularly
because the car needs lubrication if it is to run properly. (Singer
in 'The Place of Nonhumans' (Sayre and Goodpaster (eds.) Ethics
and Problems of the 21st Century Notre Dame: University of Notre
Dame Press 1979)
This is clearly a different interpretation of "interests".
With whom do you side, Singer or Goodpaster? Why?
2) Goodpaster suggests that "the core of moral concern lies in respect
for self-sustaining organisation and integration in the face of pressures
towards high entropy". But does this mean moral concern for (for
instance) computers?
3) Does this position imply impossible ethical commitments? Goodpaster
thinks not. Do you agree?
Exercise:
Please send your answer to question 1 to the discussion
site and remember that you will need to give a reason.
Paul Taylor's Respect for Nature
Goodpaster's article is a mere sketch of a possible baseline for moral
considerability. For this reason, it can't be lined up against two of
the the three axes I outlined at the beginning of the block. Whilst it
is clearly life-centred rather than sentience centred, it could be used
as the basis for either a deontological or a consequentialist position;
and although in a sense it is egalitarian, the way is left open for a
hierarchical position to be built on it.
So I want now to move on to look at one of the most important books written
in environmental ethics, Paul Taylor's Respect for Nature (Princeton:
Princeton University Press 1986). Taylor develops a complex and thought-provoking
account of human duties towards other living organisms.
Taylor's ethical system has three major strands: a belief system, a moral
attitude and rules of duty/standards of character. Fundamental to his
account is his advocacy of a human attitude of respect for nature. This
involves the recognition that humans are part of an interconnected and
interdependent ecosystem to which they are not inherently superior; and
that all organisms, as well as humans are 'teleological centres of life,
in the sense that each is a unique individual pursing its own good in
its own way' (p.100). (The word telos is a Greek word meaning something
like 'end' or 'purpose'.) All living things pursue their own ends, their
own good, and defend their own life, Taylor argues. It is on this basis
that Taylor argues all living beings have inherent worth; and this inherent
worth is equally possessed by all living organisms, since all have a good
of their own. (Note that Taylor's use of inherent worth looks like the
meaning of intrinsic value I outlined in block 1). This good, Taylor argues,
is as vital to them as a human good is to a human. On this basis, Taylor
maintains a position sometimes called biocentric equality: all organisms,
of whatever species, have the same inherent value and are entitled to
respectful treatment.
In terms of our three axes, then, Taylor's position takes the following
line:
- He's a deontologist: organisms have inherent worth which must be respected,
whatever the consequences;
- He's life-centred rather than sentience centred; all living things
have inherent worth, whether sentient or not;
- He's egalitarian: everything that is alive has inherent worth and
everything that has inherent worth has it equally. On this basis, Taylor
affirms a principle of species impartiality.
Much of Taylor's book is spent working these ideas out in more detail.
In particular, he develops four basic principles of duty to the non-human
natural world: nonmaleficence, noninterference, fidelity, and restitutive
justice. In summary, non-maleficence is the duty not to harm any particular
organisms; non-interference is the duty to refrain from constraining organisms
and to allow them to seek self-realisation unhindered; fidelity is the
duty not to break a trust placed by a wild animal in a human; and restitutive
justice is the duty to make good wrongs done to individual organisms through
human action - that is to say, when one of the other three duties has
not been followed.
Taylor's account is systematic and carefully worked through. But there
is one, enormous, obvious difficulty with it: how could anyone possibly
live such a life? Think of some of the obvious problems. How for instance
could one deal with disease, if dealing with disease means killing millions
of bacteria, all worth the same as a human life? How could one ever build
anything, since that would inevitably involve killing plants which previously
occupied the site? What about eating? And presumably Taylor's position
wouldn't support vegetarianism, since killing a plant would be as bad
as killing an animal (and cannibalism no worse, for that matter!)
In an attempt to deal with some of these questions, Taylor develops a
series of "priority principles" for resolving conflicts. These
allow for self-defence (a category into which medicine, for instance,
falls) and inevitably - to some extent at least - compromise his egalitarianism,
since he allows amongst other things for humans to construct buildings
of great cultural significance even where this results in the mass death
of organisms.
Reading 4: Paul Taylor: 'The Ethics of Respect for Nature'
in Zimmerman pp.71-86
This reading is derived from an early article Taylor wrote, prior to
developing his systematic case in Respect for Nature. It outlines some
of his key arguments, ones which he later elaborated. (For instance, in
this article he doesn't commit himself to either a consequentialist or
a deontological position; in Respect for Nature, he adopts the latter).
Clarifying Taylor's Arguments:
Check after reading this article that you could explain
the following:
- What does Taylor mean by the 'good' of an organism?
- What does he understand by the biocentric outlook
on nature?
- What does being a 'teleological centre of life' mean?
- How does Taylor use the term 'inherent worth'?
- How does he understand 'species impartiality'?
More questions about Taylor:
- Is Taylor committing some kind of naturalistic fallacy here? That
is to say, is he leaping from discussing the descriptive 'good' of an
organism to thinking of this as good in a moral sense?
- Why might Taylor have dismissed concern about non-wild organisms?
Do you think it weakens, or strengthens his case that it is wild individuals
only about whom he is concerned?
- Does it really make sense to talk about non-sentient organisms as
having their own individual perspectives on life?
- How do you respond to Taylor's attack on hierarchies of inherent worth?
Is it more 'democratic' to be egalitarian? Is the idea of a species
value hierarchy really like a human class hierarchy?
- What might the implications of Taylor's position be in practice? Could
it be made workable, or do you think it is an utterly impractical moral
position? If so, does that mean it's not worth advocating?
A Glance at some Hierarchical Positions
Before reaching the end of the block, we should just cast our eyes over
some hierarchical positions in individualist environmental ethics. In
principle, Singer, Regan and Taylor adopted the view that, as it were,
moral considerability = moral significance. If you count morally, you
count the same as everyone else. (In fact all three slip from this position
in various places, but we don't need to pursue this too closely here!)
However, a number of environmental ethicists have deliberately attempted
to develop hierarchical views, where, generally speaking, being alive
is enough to qualify for moral considerability, but having other qualities
(like sentience or consciousness) gives added moral significance - value-added,
as I suggested at the beginning of the block. We don't have space to consider
these positions in much detail here, but it's important to point them
out, and to note that both consequentialists and deontologists have adopted
such positions.
A Deontological Hierarchy of Value
Louis Lombardi in his article 'Inherent Worth, Respect and Rights' in
Environmental Ethics 5 Fall 1983 develops a deontological approach where
the value of different kinds of organisms is hierarchical. Responding
to Taylor, Lombardi argues that the "telos" possessed by a living
thing should be regarded as a capacity. And, he argues, it is a worth-giving
capacity; by which he means an organism possesses inherent worth. But,
Lombardi argues, being alive is not the only worth-giving capacity. Organisms
can have other valuable capacities, on top of being alive, that increase
inherent worth. A plant, for instance, has vegetative capacities which
give it a little 'value-added'; mammals have vegetative capacities, but
are also sentient, the added capacity to feel pleasure and pain giving
additional value; while human beings, having other additional capacities,
such as reflectiveness, have even greater value-added. Thus Lombardi constructs
a hierarchical individualist deontological environmental ethic built on
difference of capacities between species. The baseline capacity, being
alive, gives inherent worth; but other added capacities give extra worth.
A Consequentialist Hierarchy of Value
Robin Attfield is an example of a consequentialist philosopher who adopts
a hierarchical individualist postion. In fact, he adopts a new configuration
of the three axes: he combines being a consequentialist with being life-centred
and hierarchical! How does he manage this? Well, the crucial step which
enables him to do this is change the nature of the consequentialism, moving
it away from either classical utilitarianism (about pleasure and pain)
or preference utilitarianism (the satisfaction of preferences). Both these
require experience on the part of those involved. Both pleasure/pain and
the satisfaction of preferences are, after all, experiences. But Attfield
rejects experience as a necessary criterion for moral considerability.
Instead, he advocates the state of being able to flourish. Flourishing
need not be experienced, but is essential for the wellbeing of all organisms.
So what drives the consequentialism here (put in very simple form) is
maximising the flourishing of all living things. However, this is not
the end of the story for Attfield, because there are two further factors
to take into account in moral decision making. The first is a hierarchical
principle - of how psychologically complex the organism in question is.
The flourishing of more psychologically complex organisms is more important
than that of less complex organisms. But, also, the degree of significance
any proposed act has to the different organisms involved is important
too. For instance, suppose a psychologically complex animal like a human
wants to eat a less complex animal like a cow. Attfield would reject this.
Certainly, the human is more complex than the cow, and so at first sight
one might think the human should be given priority. But the need to eat
beef is a relatively trivial significance to the human (providing that
there is other food available) - it isn't fundamental to human flourishing.
But it's fundamental to the survival of the cow. On Atfield's system of
weighting then, even though the human has more capacity to flourish than
the cow, it doesn't mean that in any conflict humans will automatically
win out.
Reading Tip: A useful article developing a view like this,
on which Attfield draws, is Donald VandeVeer's article "Interspecific
Justice", published in Inquiry 1979 p. 55-79. A more detailed hierarchical
view (and one which attempts to incorporate ecosystems and species as
well) can be found in Lawrence Johnson's A Morally Deep World (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press 1991)
Summary
I. This section has looked at non-anthropocentric individualist approaches
to environmental ethics. These are ways of going about environmental ethics
that focus on the value of individual organisms or their experiences.
These individualist approaches were structured around three axes:
- consequentialist/deontological;
- sentience-centred/life centred
- egalitarian/hierarchical
II. Peter Singer developed utilitarianism to take into account the suffering
of animals. He argued that as sentient beings they are morally equal to
humans and should be treated as such. His account - in its early form
anyway - is sentience-centred and egalitarian.
III. Tom Regan developed rights theory to take into account animal rights.
He argued that animals (adult mammals) are subjects-of-a-life, have inherent
value, and should be treated as ends in themselves, never merely as means.
His account is deontological, but also sentience-centred and egalitarian.
IV. Paul Taylor argued that all living organisms have their own good,
their own telos, and that this gave them inherent worth. Humans should
adopt an attitude of respect for nature in which they recognise that they
are part of, and not superior to, a web of interdependent organisms in
the world. Part of respecting nature involves recognising the inherent
worth of non-human wild organisms, and not interfering with them or harming
them. Taylor's account is deontological, life-centred and egalitarian.
V. Finally we considered a couple of hierarchical accounts, where life
is a baseline for moral considerability, but extra capacities add value.
VI. There are, then a wide range of possible positions in individualist
environmental ethics - and not all have been filled or fully explored!
(Can you think of other possible combinations of the three axes, and arguments
for them?) However, all of these positions have been criticised by holistic
environmental ethicists.
A Concluding Exercise: before moving to the next
week’s material, have a go at thinking about the following case:
An old growth forest, with a rich ecosystem and endangered species is
about to be felled. The felling will provide employment for a number of
unemployed local people, and the area will be partly replanted with a
conifer plantation and partly used for a free-range, organic cattle farm.
- Would a) Singer b) Regan c) Taylor object? If so,
why? If not, why not?
- Which of these three positions would be most opposed
to the felling?
- Are there some ethical problems with the felling
that you want to raise but which don't seem to be taken account of in
any of these accounts?
To complete this block make sure that you have responded
to some of the exercises by sending a response to the discussion site.
Based on notes by Clare Palmer
|