I. Classical Utilitarianism
According to Classical Utlitarianism, the right action is that which
has the consequences which maximises the well-being or happiness of affected
agents i.e. the best action is that which produces the greatest improvement
in well-being.
This theory makes three distinct claims that need to be distinguished:
- It is welfarist: The only thing that is good in itself and not just
a means to another good is the happiness or well-being of individuals.
- It is consequentialist: whether an action is right or wrong is determined
solely by its consequences.
- It is an aggregative maximising approach: we choose the action that
produces the greatest total amount of well-being.
II. Two assumptions – monism and commensurability
1. Value monism
The first component of classical utilitarianism, the welfarism, claims
that there is only one thing that is of value in itself and not as a means
to another end, happiness. It appears to assume a form of value monism:
there is only one intrinsically valuable property or entity which is the
ultimate value, to which others are reducible.
Bentham’s hedonist version of welfarism identifies happiness with
pleasure and the absence of pain. It assumes the ultimate single value
will be pleasure. Other values are instrumental – means to pleasure.
Alternatively, in J.S. Mil's version of the theory pleasures differ in
quality as well as quantity BUT there is a way of comparing the value
of pleasures – that is, the preferences of individuals who are fully
informed of both.
Value monism contrasts with value pluralism.
Value pluralism: there are a number of distinct intrinsically
valuable properties, such as autonomy, knowledge, justice, equality, beauty
etc. which are not reducible to each other nor to some other ultimate
value such as pleasure.
2. Value commensurability – is there a measure of value?
The third component of classical utilitarianism, the maximising component
makes a second assumption. It appears to assume that we can ascertain
which outcome produces the greatest total amount of value. It seems to
require the existence of a common measure of value though which
different options can be compared in order to discover the greatest total
amount of value.
What kind of scale of measurement?
- Strong view: we need a cardinal scale i.e. a scale that will tell
us precisely how much value different options offer.
- Weak view: we only need an ordinal scale i.e. a scale that ranks options
Ist, 2nd, 3rd etc.
One attraction of at least some forms of value-monism is that they offer
the possibility of arriving at cardinal measures of value. Consider Bentham’s
feclific calculus discussed in week 1. Bentham's hedonistic measure of
value informs us of how much pleasure is present. It provides a cardinal
scale of value – it can tell us precisely how valuable an option
is. Pains can be measured on the same scale as pleasures, as negative
quantities. Thus it is possible to aggregate the pleasures/pains experienced
by each person, and then aggregate the pleasures/pains of a number of
people affected by some action, in this way arriving at a single result
which gives the total utility of that action.
Mill’s claim that pleasures differ in quality and not only in quantity
entails there can be no arithmetic calculus of pleasures of the kind Bentham
seeks. However, he suggests an alternative method by which pleasures can
be compared: pleasant experiences are desired, and some are desired more
than others.
3. Environmental ethics
In environmental philosophy and policy making there has been a major
conflict between those who think that any coherent and rational approach
to environmental choice requires monism and/or commensurability, and those
who allow that rational choices are possible without those assumptions.
(Light and Rolston eds. Part IV)
III. Value monism:
Arguments for value monism:
One argument for value monism is the assumption that it is required
for there to be rational decisions. There has to be a single standard
of value to compare options if there is to be rational decision making
at all. A classic statement of the position is that of J.S. Mill:
There must be some standard to determine the goodness and badness,
absolute and comparative, of ends, or objects of desires. And whatever
that standard is, there can be but one; for if there were several ultimate
principles of conduct, the same conduct might be approved of by one
of those principles and condemned by another; and there would be needed
some more general principle, as umpire between them.
Problems with this argument:
1. A general umpiring principle does not entail that there must be one
standard to determine the goodness or badness of different ends and objects.
It is possible to have many standards of value, v1, v2...vn and some
ordering principle for determining which takes precedence over others,
an umpiring rule.
E.G. Rawls’ rules introducing a lexical ordering amongst values
v1, v2...vn, such that v2 comes into play only after v1 is satisfied,
and in general any further standard of value enters consideration only
after the previous value has been satisfied
2. A fallacy - the argument involves an implicit shift in the scope of
a quantifier.
UE. For any putative practical conflict of values rationality requires
that there be a method of resolving the conflict.
does not entail
EU. Rationality requires there be a method such that for any practical
conflict the method resolves the conflict.
The inference of EU from UE involves a shift in the scope of the quantifiers:
An example of the fallacy: ‘Everybody loves somebody’ does
not entail ‘There is somebody that everybody loves’.
III. Value pluralism
Value pluralism: There are a number of distinct intrinsically valuable
properties, such as autonomy, knowledge, justice, equality, beauty etc.
which are not reducible to each other nor to some other ultimate value
such as pleasure.
A thought in favour of pluralism: the richness of our evaluative language
cannot be reduced to some single value conferring property.
Consider the diversity of evaluative concepts that are employed in the
appraisal of our environments and the variety of practices that inform
our relationships to our environments that this reflects. We use then
a rich vocabulary to appraise the environments we live in, from and with.
- biological and ecological sciences - biodiversity, species richness,
integrity, fragility, health.
- aesthetic traditions - tones of colour, such as the contrasting browns
and reds of autumn, the subtle shifts in shades of green in spring,
the dappled sunlight in woodlands; the forms and shapes of nature such
as the ruggedness of mountains, the gentleness of hills, the landscapes
shaped by stone wall and terrace; the sounds such as birdsong and river
over rocks; and textures such as the roughness of gritstone and the
sharp and smooth of limestone.
- a place based vocabulary - a location might be valued for being evocative
of the past.
These can conflict in particular conservation problems. Consider the
following conflicts in nature conservation in Wales:
- The spread of rhododendron around Beddgelert. The rhododendron is
a superb landscape feature and draws many visitors when it flowers.
From the nature conservation view it is an alien Himalayan intruder
that spreads quickly and under whose dense thicket little else grows,
destroying local ecological systems.
- The disused slate-quarries on the Llanberis side of Elidir Fawr. From
both landscape and ecological perspectives there is very little to said
for them. They form a huge industrial scar up a mountainside and at
present contain very little of interest to the natural scientist. Plans
to landscape the quarries were partially implemented. Some of the local
people, however, were very unhappy about this, on the grounds that landscaping
literally covers up the past. The quarries embody a sense of place and
past for a community.
Question:
Could that variety be reduced to some single value?
How should conflicts between such values be resolved?
One possible response would be to say, "There is an ultimate value
at work here – well-being. The different values all make a contribution
to human well-being, or more widely the well-being of individual sentient
beings. Well-being remains the ultimate value".
Yet a reply to this might emphasise well-being and pluralism: Some apparently
monistic views may be themselves pluralistic when unpacked. Objective
list accounts of well-being typically assume that there are a number of
components of well-being - autonomy, knowledge, personal relationships
with friends and family, and so on. Each is valuable in itself and not
reducible to any other. Welfare or well-being are covering terms for the
various valuable components of life.
IV. Trading-off values
If value-pluralism is true, does it follow that there is no single measure
of value, that value commensurability also falls? Not necessarily. Value-commensurability
is compatible with at least some forms of pluralism if one assumes that
different values can be traded-off with each other.
What is it to say that values can be traded-off against each other? There
are a variety of ultimate values, but we can compare those values and
say that a loss in one dimension of value is equal to a gain in another.
Here we can introduce the idea of a trade-off schedule:
a loss of so much in one value is compensated for by a gain of so much
in another. In making choices or expressing preferences between different
options which involve losses and gains in different values, we are implicitly
trading–off different values.
Universal currency
If such a trade-off schedule exists value commensuralibility may be
possible. What we need is a universal currency for that
trade, some measuring rod which we can use to measure the different rates
at which losses and gains in different dimensions of value evidence themselves
and then put them on a common scale.
Exercise: Conflicting values in forestry management
in the U.K. The context is one of conflicting values.
- different biodiversity objectives –
- increasing the diversity of native tree species in forests is
in conflict with the aim of protecting the native species of red
squirrel which fares better than the immigrant grey squirrel in
conifer plantations or the protection of the goshawk which flourishes
in spruce plantation. biodiversity considerations themselves conflict
with others:
- landscape considerations;
- the use value of forests as a timber resource;
- specific historical and cultural meanings as a place
for a particular community.
How are such conflicts between different objectives
to be settled?
Is there a measure of value that could be used
to trade-off losses in one dimension with gains in another?
The economist in the utilitarian tradition suggests that money can act
as such a universal measuring rod.
Environmental economist: Given the existence of competing values and
objectives - biodiversity, landscape, timber, cultural meanings, historical
and scientific values and so on - resolution requires some common measure
of comparison for giving each its due against each other. Certain economists
argue that monetary price is the best measure for making those trade-offs.
The use of the measure does not entail that there is only one thing of
value, in particular that only money is of value. Rather money serves
as a measure of the exchange rate between different values.
Blocked exchange and constitutive incommensurabilities
Can values be traded like this?
Problem.
The currency of some values may not be convertible into the currency of
others. Some exchanges are blocked. The point is of particular significance
for the use of money measures. There are many values which simply cannot
be converted into a monetary equivalent.
Money is not a neutral measuring rod for comparing the losses and gains
in different values. Values cannot all be caught within a monetary currency.
Note this is an argument against monetary measures, not yet to measures
in general.
Certain kinds of social relations and evaluative commitments are constituted
by particular kinds of shared understanding which are such that they are
incompatible with market relations. Social loyalties, for example, to
friends and to family, are constituted by a refusal to treat them as commodities
that can be bought or sold. Given what love and friendship are, and given
what market exchanges are, one cannot buy love or friendship.
Some environmental goods are of this nature – see 511
week 2.
V. Value-pluralism, consequentialism, and the alternatives
Trade and consequentialism
The metaphor of trading values suggests a particular consequentialist
framing of choices. What aim to produce a state of affairs with the greatest
amount of value, and we do this by comparing the gains and losses of different
dimensions of value, trading these off until we arrive at a result that
produces the greatest gains in values over losses in values. The account
is pluralist about values – there are a variety of different values
– but by exchanging gains and losses in these distinct dimensions
of value, we can still arrive at some notion of the outcome with the highest
total value.
Other approaches to ethics, deontological and virtue based approaches,
do not lend themselves to the trading metaphor in this sense.
Deontology and value-pluralism
Deontological ethics can take both monist and pluralist forms.
Monist: There is one basic obligation, for example that we treat persons
as end in themselves, and that other obligations are derivative on this
obligation.
Pluralist: (1) there are a variety of basic obligations, say obligations
of justice, obligations to improve the well-being of others, obligations
not to injure others, obligations to develop one’s own projects,
obligations that arise from special relations, for example of parents
to children, obligations that arise from previous acts, say of making
a promise, or making right a previous wrong, or from gratitude, and so
on, and (2) these obligations are not reducible to each other or some
other ultimate principle.
Resolving conflict: resolving a value conflict is rather a matter of
which obligation has the stronger pull on an agent in a particular context.
Exercise:
Consider a parent who spends time with her children on holiday that she
could be spending on an action of an environmental cause she also pursues
and which benefits many more people.
Question: How should such a conflict be resolved?
One response: She does not do so necessarily because she trades-off the
value of being with her children against those values she would produce
for other people, nor because she believes that her action produces a
more valuable state of affairs. It is rather that her obligations to her
children in some cases over-ride those of others.
An agent may compare the importance of different obligations that make
demands on her. However, it is not a matter of trading-off values in order
to arrive at the outcome with the highest value. Rather it is a matter
of the relations one stands with respect to different individuals and
groups and considering the competing claims they make on you as an agent.
Virtue ethics and value pluralism
Virtue ethics can take monist and pluralist forms.
Monist: there is just one ultimate virtue, such as intelligence, and
that all other virtues, courage, justice, generosity, autonomy, kindness,
and so on are ultimately different ways of exhibiting that virtue.
Pluralist: There are many basic virtues that are not reducible to each
other or some other ultimate virtue.
Resolving conflict: From a virtues perspective what matters is what kind
of person one should be.
Exercise: How might a virtues ethics respond to the conflicts described
in the previous two exercises?
VI. Structural pluralism
As different ethical theories are usually presented, each assumes that
there is a structure to ethical theory with certain ethical primitives.
They are reductionist in that they offer different accounts of what
these primitive concepts of ethics are, and then attempt to show how other
ethical concepts can be reduced to those primitive concepts. Consequentialism:
‘What state of affairs ought I bring about?’ The primitives
of ethical theory are states of affairs. What is intrinsically good or
bad are states of affairs. Actions and states of character are instrumentally
valuable as a means to producing the best state of affairs.
Deontology: ‘What acts am I obliged to perform or not perform?’
The primitives of ethical theory are the acts of agents. What is intrinsically
good are certain acts we are obliged to perform and what is intrinsically
bad are certain acts which are impermissible. States of character are
instrumentally valuable as dispositions to perform right acts. A state
of affairs is right if it is the outcome of morally just acts.
Virtues ethic: ‘What kind of person should I be?’ The primitives
of ethical theory are dispositions of character. The basic good of ethical
life is the development of a certain character. A right action is the
act a virtuous agent would perform; the best state of affairs one that
a good agent would aim to bring about.
Why should one believe that there are primitives in ethics of this kind?
One answer is a certain picture of what an ethical theory should be like
– like a scientific or mathematical theory, it should have a particular
structure:
- A number of basic explanatory concepts and propositions
- Other ethical concepts and propositions are shown be derivable from
those basic concepts and propositions.
- The structure of the theory will give some kind of order and organisation
to our ethical reflections on particular cases.
Here is one influential expression of that conception of ethics that has
been influential in environmental ethics.
An ethical system S is, near enough, a propositional system (i.e. a
structured set of propositions) or theory which includes (like individuals
of a theory) a set of values and (like postulates of a theory) a set
of general evaluative judgements concerning conduct, typically what
is obligatory, permissible and wrong, of what are rights, what is valued
and so forth. (R. Sylvan ‘Is There a Need for a New, and Environmental,
Ethic’ in Light and Holmes Rolston III, p 49)
Why should it be thought that an ethical theory should look like
this?
Answer – to give rational coherence to ethical reflection. However,
one might accept the need for some for a reasoned ethical reflection without
assuming that it take the form of an ethical theory modelled on a scientific
or mathematical theory.
Reasons for scepticism:
1. Different primitives cannot be logically isolated in the way that these
theories require.
- One cannot state why a virtue like courage is a virtue without mentioning
that it involves standing firm against certain independently defined
harmful states of affair.
- One cannot say what is morally wrong with acts like torture without
reference to the pain in which it issues.
- Some states of affairs themselves can only be characterised as wrong
in terms of their involving failure to respect persons or cruelty of
character.
2. The different ethical theories call upon different sources of value
Nagel 'The Fragmentation of Value'
There are a number of distinct types of value:
- Specific obligations that arise from special relations and roles.
Obligations to my children, obligations as a lecturer.
- Constraints on actions deriving from rights of persons. E.g. rights
not to be tortured, assaulted etc.
- Utility - consideration of the outcomes of one’s action on
the general welfare.
- Perfectionist ends – the intrinsic value of certain achievements,
such as a scientific discovery, a work of art, a novel etc.
- Commitments to one’s own projects
Nagel’s argument: These are irreducible to each other because they
have different sources – we can view the world from different perspectives
– individual, relational, impersonal, ideal etc.
A fundamental division he draws is that between personal or agent-centred
perspectives and impersonal or outcome-centred perspectives.
Agent-centred (1,2, and 5): when we view actions from
the perspective as an agent there are reasons for that agent to perform
or restrain from certain actions.
Consider the agent-based restrictions on action discussed in the last
chapter.
While it may be better from an impartial perspective that there are fewer
chemical weapons, that one indian dies rather than six, that one child
suffers torture rather than several persons suffer the consequences of
a bomb blast there are constraints on what we can oblige or permit an
agent to do to realise those goals.
Outcome-centred (3 and 4): when we view actions from
an impersonal perspective concerned only with the value of a state of
affairs brought about, independently of the nature of action that brought
it about or who brought it about.
Nagel’s view – Neither of these different perspectives can
be abandoned, neither is reducible to the other, neither is reducible
to a third perspective. The perspectives are incommensurable.
Structural pluralism: pluralism can exist not just within
different dimensions of value - between different valued states of affair,
between different obligations, between different virtues – but also
between them. There can be conflicts involving what will produce the best
outcome, constraints on types of action and different states of character.
V. Value-pluralism and value conflict:
How might conflicts between plural values be resolved?
For a discussion of some different approaches see module 511
week 2.
Is a resolution of value conflicts always possible?
Moral dilemmas: Is it possible for a person to be in a situation in which
she ought to do A and ought to do B but cannot do both?
Two views:
1. Against moral dilemmas While there maybe apparent
moral dilemmas all such conflicts are resolvable. This is a long standing
theme in philosophy and one finds this view developed in all three traditions;
Consequentialism: For the utilitarian, the principle of utility will
resolve apparent conflicts – the right action is that which produces
the greatest improvement in well-being: ‘If utility is the ultimate
source of moral obligations, utility may be invoked to decide between
them when their demands are incompatible’ (J.S. Mill Utilitarianism
chapter 2, final paragraph)
Deontology: For Kant moral duties cannot conflict, since they express
what it is morally necessary for us to do. ‘A conflict of duties
(collisio officiorum seu obligationum) would be such a relation between
them that one would wholly or partially abolish the other. Now as duty
and obligation are notions which express the objective practical necessity
of certain actions, and as two opposite rules cannot be necessary at the
same time, but if it is a duty to act according to one of them, it is
then not only not a duty but inconsistent with duty to act according to
the other; it follows that a conflict of duties and obligations is inconceivable
(obligationes non colliduntur).’ (Kant Introduction To The Metaphysic
Of Morals; And Preface
to The Metaphysical Elements of Ethics)
Virtue ethics: The unity of the virtues entails that there can be no
ultimate conflicts between the virtues (Aristotle Nicomachean
Ethics Book 6, chapter 13).
2. Arguments for the ineliminability of moral dilemmas:
Plural and incommensurable values: Given the existence
of a plurality of incommensurable values a resolution of conflicts between
values may not be possible. Reason cannot ensure for us in advance that
conflicts of values can be resolved and tragic choice avoided. The question
‘How do we resolve moral conflicts?’ may be the wrong question.
We may at the end of reflection have to accept that we are in a situation
in which whatever we do a wrong will be done.
Ethical residues: Blameless individuals can find themselves
in situations whatever they do they do something wrong – and hence
that emotions such as regret, guilt and shame are appropriation. The existence
of ethical dilemmas may result in a number of ethical residues –
shame at having to do something that runs against our deepest conception
of the kind of person we aspired to be, or regret that we act with integrity
in a situation in which we know the worst will befall us, or guilt where
we find ourselves wronging some individual.
For further discussion of moral dilemmas see:
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-dilemmas/#4
For a discussion of moral dilemmas in Greek tragedy see:
http://www.univ.trieste.it/~etica/2001_1/cowley.html
Consider
some of the examples of environmental examples we have discussed this
far in the course. How might those conflicts be resolved?
Can they all be resolved?
What responses are appropriate if they cannot be resolved?
|