I. Classical Utilitarianism:
The right action is that which has the consequences which maximises the
well-being or happiness of affected agents i.e. the best action is that
which produces the greatest improvement in well-being.
The theory makes three distinct claims that need to be distinguished:
1. It is welfarist: The only thing that is good in itself
and not just a means to another good is the happiness or well-being of
individuals.
2. It is consequentialist: whether an action is right
or wrong is determined solely by its consequences.
3. It is an aggregative maximising approach: we choose
the action that produces the greatest total amount of well-being.
Consequentialism
Whether an action is right or wrong depends upon the ends it is used
to achieve. Actions as such, without regard to the states of affairs they
bring about, have no moral value, positive or negative, but are morally
neutral. They have only instrumental value. They can never be wrong in
themselves. They are means to what is of intrinsically valuable, for what
is valuable for its own sake.
Consequentialism is quite independent of how what is intrinsically good
is characterised – one needn’t defend the classical utilitarian
view of what is good. It says whatever is intrinsically good, the right
action is the one that promotes that good.
Thought in favour of consequentialism: what else could determine what
is good other than the value it promotes? Wouldn’t it be irrational
or inconsistent to say – ‘I value A, but I don’t think
I should act to promote that value’?
II. Problems for consequentialism:
A. Consequentialism permits too much:
Example 1: A ruthless head of a large corporation operating with the
licence of a corrupt political regime is about to order the release of
a cocktail of toxic chemicals into a water supply. However, he is a good
family man. The only effective way to stop him is to kidnap and threaten
violence on an innocent member of his family.
Example2: A terrorist has planted a bomb in a busy city centre. He refuses
to say where it is. However, he is a good family man. The only way to
discover where it is planted is to torture an innocent member of his family.
It might seem that form the utilitarian perspective the calculation of
consequences really does show that torturing an innocent individual would
do more good than harm, or prevent more harm than it caused, to all those
affected, then it is the right thing to do.
Rejection of consequentialism: there are acts one ought not to perform
even if their consequences are good or even the best - some acts are intrinsically
wrong, wrong in themselves: killing the innocent, torturing the innocent,
lying, promise-breaking, for instance. Such actions may sometimes have
overall good consequences, but that does not make them right.
Deontological ethics: To hold a deontological ethic
is to accept that there are constraints on performing certain kinds of
actions even where those actions produce a greater value than not performing
them. The basic ethical question is ‘What acts am I obliged to perform
or not perform?’.
What is the problem? The moral standing of individuals
Individuals have a moral standing which cannot be over-ridden for the
purposes of promoting the greater good. As Rawls has it, this ‘Each
person has an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of
society as a whole cannot override’. (J. Rawls A Theory of Justice
p.3). One source of this thought is Kantian:
Now I say that man, and in general every rational being, exists as
an end in himself, not merely as a means for arbitrary use by this or
that will: he must in all his actions, whether they are directed to
himself or to other rational beings, always be viewed at the same time
as an end. All the objects of inclination have only a conditioned value;
for if there were not these inclinations and the needs grounded on them,
their objects would be valueless. Inclinations themselves, as sources
of needs, are so far from having an absolute value to make them desirable
for their own sake that it must rather be the universal wish of every
rational being to be wholly free from them. Thus the value of all objects
that can be produced by our action is always conditioned. Beings whose
existence depends, not on our will, but on nature, have none the less,
if they are non-rational beings, only a relative value as means and
are consequently called things. Rational beings, on the other hand,
are called persons because their nature already marks them out as ends
in themselves - that is, as something that ought not to be used merely
as a means - and consequently imposes to that extent a limit on all
arbitrary treatment of them (and is an object of reverence). (I. Kant
Groundwork
of the Metaphysic of Morals, ch 2)
Rights: The Kantian view that individuals are ends
in themselves that cannot be treated merely as means to the promotion
of the greater good is often stated in the language of rights. Individuals
have rights that cannot be overridden by the greater good.
Question:
Could this Kantian approach provide the basis for an
environmental ethics? How far can the Kantian approach be extended to
non-humans?
Deontological ethics and environmental concern
There are three main moves that have been made to extend the deontological
position to environmental concern.
- Extend the sphere of human rights to include rights to certain environmental
goods. A right to an environment that is necessary to basic health and
well-being is a human right that cannot be overridden for other goods.
(See T. Hayward, 2004, Constitutional Environmental Rights
Oxford: OUP).
- Extend rights to include rights of sentient non-human animals (See
T. Regan, 1988 The Case for Animal Rights London: Routledge)
- Extend rights to include rights of all living things. (See P. Taylor,
1986 Respect for Nature Princeton, Princeton University Press)
We will discuss approaches 2 and 3 in detail in week 5.
John Rawls' Theory of Justice (TJ)
‘Original position’ and ‘the veil of ignorance’:
How should we determine what principles should govern the ‘basic
structure’ of a just society?
Rawls answer: those we would arrive at in ‘original position’
– a hypothetical situation in which rational disinterested persons
choose to agree to behind ‘a veil of ignorance' (implements the
idea of impartiality):
Veil of ignorance: ‘It is assumed that parties do not know certain
kinds of particular facts. First of all, no one knows his place in society,
his class position or social status; nor does he know his fortune in the
distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence and strength,
and the like. Nor again does anyone know his conception of the good, the
particulars of his rational plan of life, or even the special features
of his psychology such as aversion to risk or liability to optimism and
pessimism’ (TJ section 24, emphasis added)
[NB – this is a hypothetical device for arriving
at principles that are both fair and neutral (and hence able to adjudicate
between competing conception of the good.)]
Thin and thick theory of the good
What do individuals know? (One couldn’t reason from a completely
blank sheet.)
They know that their society is subject to the circumstances of justice
(limited altruism and moderate scarcity) and ‘general facts about
human society’.
Distinction: Thin and thick theory of the good. (TJ 15 and 60)
Thin theory of the good: those ‘primary’ goods which are required
by any rational person to carry out whatever their particular plan of
life may be.
Thick theory of the good: the detailed specification of what makes life
valuable for a person.
Primary goods: ‘Primary goods...are things which it is supposed
a rational man wants whatever else he wants...’ ‘Whatever
one’s systems of ends, primary goods are necessary means.’
‘While the persons in the original position do not know their conception
of the good, they do know...that they prefer more rather than less primary
goods’
What are the primary goods?: ‘rights and liberties, opportunities
and powers, income and wealth [and] a sense of one’s own worth’
Principles of justice
What principles would be chosen in the original position?
'1. Each person has an equal right to a fully adequate scheme of equal
basic liberties which is compatible with a similar scheme of liberties
for
all.
2. Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions.
First, they must be attached to offices and positions open to all under
conditions of fair equality of opportunity [the opportunity principle];
and second they must be to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged
members of society [the difference principle].’
The principles are lexically ordered: the satisfaction
of the first principle has priority over the satisfaction of the second
and the first part of the second is prior to the second part of the second.
Links for discussions of Rawls:
There is a good resource page on John Rawls at: http://www.policylibrary.com/rawls/index.htm
For a good overview and discussion of his work see Nussbaum's, The
Enduring Significance of John Rawls:
Question:
How far could Rawls’ approach be employed to capture
environmental concerns?
B. Consequentialism demands too much:
Bernard Williams example: George is an unemployed chemist of poor health,
with a family who are suffering in virtue of his being unemployed. An
older chemist, knowing of the situation tells George he can swing him
a decently paid job in a laboratory doing research into biological and
chemical warfare. George is deeply opposed to biological and chemical
warfare, but the older chemist points out that if George does not take
the job then another chemist who is a real zealot for such research will
get the job, and push the research along much faster than would the reluctant
George. Should George take the job?
For the consequentialist, given any plausible account of the good, the
right thing to do is obvious: George should take the job. That will produce
better consequence both for his family and the world in general.
Williams To take the job would be to undermine George's integrity. He
must treat his own projects and commitments as just so many desires to
be put into the calculus with others.
It is absurd to demand of such a man, when the sums come in from the
utility network which the projects of others have in part determined,
that he should just step aside from his own project and decision and
acknowledge the decision which the utilitarian calculation requires.
It is to alienate him in a real sense from his actions and the source
of his action in his own convictions. It is to make him into a channel
between the input of everyone's projects, including his own, and an
output of optimific decision; but this is to neglect the extent to which
his actions and his decisions have to be seen as the actions and decisions
which flow from the projects and attitudes with which he is most closely
identified. It is thus, in the most literal sense, an attack on his
integrity.( B. Williams 'A Critique of Utilitarianism' pp.116-117 in
J.J.C. Smart and B. Williams Utilitarianism For and Against)
Consider the following example from Bernard Williams:
Jim finds himself in the central square of a small
South American town. Tied up against the wall are a row of twenty Indians,
most terrified, a few defiant, in front of them several armed men in
uniform. A heavy man in a sweat-stained khaki shirt turns out to be
the captain in charge and, after a good deal of questioning of Jim which
establishes that he got there by accident while on a botanical expedition,
explains that the Indians are a random group of the inhabitants who,
after recent acts of protest against the government, are just about
to be killed to remind other possible protesters of the advantages of
not protesting. However, since Jim is an honoured visitor from another
land, the captain is happy to offer him a guest's privilege of killing
one of the Indians himself. If Jim accepts, then as a special mark of
the occasion, the other Indians will be let off. Of course, if Jim refuses,
then there is no special occasion, and Pedro here will do what he was
about to do when Jim arrived, and kill them all. Jim, with some desperate
recollection of schoolboy fiction, wonders whether if he got hold of
a gun, he could hold the captain, Pedro, and the rest of the soldiers
to threat, but it is quite clear from the set-up that nothing of that
kind is going to work: any attempt at that sort of thing will mean that
all the Indians will be killed, and himself. The men against the wall,
and the other villagers, understand the situation, and are obviously
begging him to accept. What should he do?
Questions:
What
does the utilitarian say that Jim should do?
What do you think Jim should do?
If your answers to the questions are the same are there
differences between the reasons you offer and those of the utilitarian?
Can from the utilitarian perspective Jim attach any
special ethical significance to the fact that he is the one who pulls
the trigger?
What is the problem? Agent-based restrictions on action
While it may be better from an impartial perspective that there are fewer
chemical weapons, that one indian dies rather than six, that one child
suffers torture rather than several persons suffer the consequences of
a bomb blast there are constraints on what we can oblige or permit an
agent to do to realise those goals.
On what grounds can a person make that kind of claim? One justification
of that position is that of the ‘virtues ethic’. To hold a
virtues ethic is to take the question 'what kind of person should I be?'
to be the basic question in ethical deliberation. Primitives of ethical
appraisal include the excellences of character, the virtues.
A virtues ethic: The basic ethical question is 'what
sort of person should I be' and an answer to that question cites excellences
of character, virtues, to be developed and defects of character, vices,
to be avoided.
On this line of argument, integrity, the virtue of our chemist, is of
basic value, which cannot be overridden by consequentialist considerations,
since it is one of those basic excellences of character.
Question: How might a virtues ethic be extended to include
non-human beings?
Virtues and environmental concern
Starting question: what it is for us to do well as human agents, what
sorts of person should we be?
Answer: specify a certain range of dispositions of character that are
constitutive of a good human life: sensitivity, courage, loyalty, good
judgement and so on.
Many of those dispositions of character will be exhibited in having particular
responses that are proper to other humans. For example, someone who perceives
the undeserved pain of a fellow human being and feels no response of sympathy
or compassion will lack one of the dispositions of character that make
for a good human life. In an extreme case they would exhibit a psychopathic
character. Someone with those dispositions would miss out on many of the
goods of human life such as friendship, love, relations with kin and human
solidarity.
Some such dispositions of character that are part of what makes for a
good human life might include dispositions and capacities to respond appropriately
to beings in the non human world. This will include sensitivity and compassion
to the suffering of other sentient beings. However, it might also involve
a wider set of dispositions and responses to the non-human world, attitudes
of awe towards the larger universe of which we are just a part, or of
wonder at the complexity and interdependence of particular places and
living things. (See R. Hursthouse, Ethics, Humans and Other Animals
London: Routledge; J. O’Neill, 1993 Ecology, Policy and
Politics: Human Well-Being and the Natural World London, Routledge)
III. Possible consequentialist responses
Question: what justification would you give for respecting individuals’
rights or integrity?
Possible answer: because the world in which rights and integrity are respected
is a better world than one in which they are not. There are good consequentialist
reasons for respecting rights and integrity.
1. Indirect utilitarianism:
One may have utilitarian reasons for not using utilitarian calculation
in making particular decisions. One will, however, use utilitarian calculation
in deciding, in a cool hour, what rules, and habits it is best to adopt
for general use.
Parallels: paradox of hedonism: Consider the person who in making pleasure
their aim, misses out on pleasure (think of the party goer, who is so
desperate to have a good time, that they never get one). It may be that
if one wants happiness one should not aim at happiness.
But I now thought that this end [happiness] was only to be attained
by not making it the direct end. Those only are happy (I thought) who
have their minds fixed on some object other than their own happiness....Aiming
thus at something else, they find happiness along the way.... Ask yourself
whether you are happy, and you cease to be so. J. S. Mill Autobiography
See also the paradox of self-realisation, paradox of success.
The indirect utilitarianism insists on the distinction between utilitarianism
as a criterion of rightness and utilitarianism understood as a decision
procedure. That is the indirect utilitarian distinguishes between (i)
the criterion by which an action or policy is judged to be right; (ii)
the decision making method that is used, on a particular occasion, to
decide which action or policy to adopt.
The indirect utilitarian says that the criterion (i) is the Principle
of Utility, but that the best way to ensure that an action satisfies this
criterion may be to apply a simple principle, or to follow the moral habits
one is brought up to follow. The distinction matters since utilitarian
outcomes are unlikely to be achieved by following 'utilitarian' decision
making procedures.
Why?
- Constraints on information, time and uncertainty which mean that
it will be impossible to calculate and weigh all the consequences of
all the alternatives.
- Indirect results of absence of rules of justice e.g. insecurity.
- Collective choice problems: In a number of situations if individuals
pursue actions that aim to maximise happiness, the result will not maximise
happiness. Consider paradoxes of altruism. In a marginally overcrowded
and sinking life-boat each individual thinks they will make the difference
and jumps out to maximise the total good. The result is that everybody
drowns. Some standard rule of priority, say of the youngest to stay,
will produce a better result than each acting in terms of a utilitarian
calculation. (See also the tragedy of the commons)
- Corruption on moral sensibilities: to engage in consequentialist
reasoning may corrupt the individuals' moral sensibilities and dispositions.
The best utilitarian outcomes are produced by communities that are not
inhabited by instrumental reasoners.
Hence, it may be that utilitarians should not use utilitarian decision
making procedures.
For example: the indirect utilitarian might argue that the best decision
rule for achieving the maximum of welfare is one that accords rights recognises
the special importance of certain basic interests as essential components
of happiness. Consider the following argument of Mill's for rights to
protect those interests of an individual which are fundamental to his
or her welfare.
When we call anything a person's right, we mean that he has a valid
claim on society to protect him in the possession of it, either by the
force of law, or by that of education and opinion. If he has what we
consider a sufficient claim, on whatever account, to have something
guaranteed to him by society, we say he has a right to it. . . Justice
is a name for certain classes of moral rules, which concern the essentials
of human well-being more nearly, and are therefore of more absolute
obligation, than any other rules for the guidance of life; and the notion
that we have found to be of the essence of the idea of justice, that
of a right residing in an individual, implies and testifies to this
more binding obligation. (J.S. Mill Utilitarianism ch 5)
2. Extend the account of the good:
The problem with the counter-example may lie in the particular account
of what is intrinsically valuable rather than consequentialism. That is
they are objections to the welfarism and maximising components of utilitarianism,
not the consequentialism.
So one might say – certain rights (‘goal rights’ Sen),
personal integrity, equality, etc. are valuable in themselves. The counter-examples
show up a restricted account of what the ultimate goods are, not a problem
in consequentialism as such.
Question:
How adequate are the responses made on behalf of consequentialism
to counterexamples?
|