Away MAVEThe Distance Mode of MA in Values and the Environment at Lancaster University 401 Ethical Theory and Philosophical MethodFeminist Ethics |
|||||
|Home|Aims and Outcomes|Module Description|Tutor Details|Biblio|Assessment|Resources|Discussion
So far in this module, we’ve looked at the more traditional ways of going about doing ethics: utilitarian consequentialism, Kantian deontology and virtue theory. Now we’re going to go on and look at a more recent approach – or group of approaches – towards thinking about ethical questions – feminist ethics. This part of the module falls into three sections: 1) a general introduction to feminist ethics; 2) a study of two readings from Sterba’s book Ethics: The Big Questions, and finally 3) a shorter section on moral discussion and dialogue, which draws on an article by the feminist writer Alison Jagger in Sterba’s book, and uses it to think about how one might deal with conflicting moral positions.
|
Now read Annette Baier “What do women want in a moral theory?” in Sterba (ed.) p.325-331 |
Baier, like many of those writing in feminist ethics, begins with reflection on Carol Gilligan, and finds in women’s ethical writing “the voice Gilligan heard, made reflective and philosophical”. This leads her on to make a number of interesting points it’s worth thinking about further.
She talks, on p.326, about what constitutes writing a complete moral theory, and comments at the end:
“Most of what are recognised as the current moral theories are also incomplete, since they do not purport to be yet really comprehensive. Wrongs to animals and wrongful destruction of our physical environment are put to one side…and in most “liberal” theories there are only handwaves concerning our proper attitude to our children, to the ill, to our relatives, friends and lovers.”
Question: Are the moral theories you’ve considered so far on this unit really incomplete in this sense? Is “not covering” such areas a sign of an incomplete moral theory? Are there reasons (which Baier doesn’t suggest) why women might not yet have produced systematic moral theories?
Baier then moves on to think about what a systematic female theorist might produce as a moral theory and suggests that it would be an “ethics of love” which would be acceptable both to “reflective women and reflective men”. Such a theory, she suggests, should “swallow up” previous ethical theories by taking into account male insights (which male philosophers always have put forward) and female insights (which male philosophers have ignored.) To do this, women’s moral theories will have to connect “love” and “obligation”.
Discussion point: Arguments like this show how heavily Gilligan’s work has influenced the premises of some approaches to feminist ethics. Yet it seems like a number of difficulties present themselves. In associating women with the language of love, and men with obligation; and women’s ethical concerns with the private sphere whilst men’s is with the public, aren’t traditional ideas of male/female roles being reinforced? Does the idea that women’s ethics is truly inclusive of male and female concerns overcome this difficulty?
Baier suggests that appropriate trust should lie at the heart of an inclusive ethics of love:
“the variety of goods we may trust others not to take from us, the variety and sorts of security or insurance we have when we do, the sorts of defenses or potential defenses we lay down when we trust, the various conditions for reasonable trust of various types...”
these, she suggests might form the basis of an ethical theory, and fits well into an ethics of love.
Questions:
What could be meant by love here? Is love something one can theorise about? Can one choose to have it or not have it? Is it understood here as a feeling, a practice, or both?
Do you think “Who should trust whom with what and why?” (p.329) makes a good central question for a moral theory? Can you think of ethical situations which might not be well served by it, or where it might not be an appropriate question? Do you think it really does “swallow up” the more traditional approaches of utilitarianism and Kantianism or, more generally, “men’s and women’s moral intuitions”?
Now read Joan Tronto “What can feminists learn about morality from caring?” in Sterba p. 346-356 |
This article looks in more detail at an aspect of feminist ethics of which we have already heard a great deal: caring. I want to use this article, on which there will be quite extensive reflection, as a basis for thinking in more detail about caring as an approach to ethics. Tronto provides a very helpful way in to considering a number of questions in more depth. Amongst other things, Tronto explores what caring might mean in a feminist context, and some of the pitfalls which might arise if the term isn’t used carefully. She also makes a useful distinction between feminist and feminine.
Tronto suggests that “caring” is a word we use in two different ways: caring about things, and caring for things. In these instances, she suggests, caring has something in common: an “ongoing responsibility and commitment”; the assumption of a burden. She notes that in all forms of its use caring is a relational term. However, we can distinguish “caring about” as a general term for less concrete objects from “caring for” – a specific, particular object. She relates “caring for” to the needs of others, whilst caring about has no such relationship; and she suggests that our society relates “caring for” to women and “caring about” to men.
In the course of this discussion, Tronto raises a number of intriguing issues about caring. She suggests that some forms of caring-for have been privatised and marketised, leaving providers of market services to feign care.
Question:
in what sense is this care feigned? What does the use of this term tell us about Tronto’s idea of what caring is?
Tronto then argues that caring is not necessarily a moral issue. This is clearly the case where “caring about” is concerned. I might care about whether Martina Hingis won the tennis, but this isn’t a moral concern. Caring for, though, Tronto suggests does raise moral issues. And here, again, she makes some interesting comments. She suggests, for instance, that social expectations of what constitutes caring-for may be based on class, race and gendered assumptions. She also counters the argument that caring seems to be seen as something we have to do, rather than something we choose to do, and hence is not part of the moral sphere. In countering this argument, she focuses on the question not only whether one ought to care for someone in any particular set of circumstances (a more common question in ethics) but also on the question how one should care, that is to say the practice of caring. Even if one were to accept that there are situations where one has no choice about caring, clearly there are many choices about how one should care, and how (for instance) one should deal with conflicting caring concerns.
This leads Tronto to think in more detail about the nature of caring; on p. 349 she outlines 3 areas in which “caring for another raises questions about the moral life”:
a) the necessary attentiveness to the other’s needs;
b) questions about autonomy and authority;
c) problems which arise out of the particularity of caring for another.
Let’s look at these in turn:
Attentiveness:
Attentiveness to the needs of the other is central to “caring for” as Tronto understands it. She maintains that this view is distinct from those of more traditional forms of ethics because:
Question:
Do you think Tronto is right about this? Doesn’t utilitarianism, for instance, work by adding up the particular pains and pleasures of others?
Because of the very specific nature of this knowledge needed to care for, attentiveness is centrally significant. Attentiveness means attentiveness not only to what the other thinks they need, but what they really need; and Tronto stresses the difficulty of achieving this because of the ways in which our own needs and perceptions which we may not fully understand ourselves, cloud our vision of others.
This leads Tronto on to consider some of the more difficult questions raised by an ethics of care:
How far should one sacrifice oneself? How far should one put one’s own concerns in the back seat in order to care for others? As we have already seen, this is the kind of question lesbian ethicists ask about the ethics of care: is this a re-validation of the cultural position women have found themselves in where they are the carers at the expense of their own interests and needs? And what about where someone sacrifices themselves in care to someone who abuses their care? Aren’t there times when it is appropriate to stop caring (and perhaps think about self justice?) Marilyn Friedman, for instance, emphasises the potential for violence and harm in caring relationships. Nel Noddings maintains that there is no obligation to care if caring cannot reach completion in the other, that is, if there is no acknowledgement of the caring in the individual being cared for. (The latter position is one which Tronto here declares to be “clearly wrong”).
What about the risk to oneself? A further, related question concerns the degree of risk involved in adopting the kind of concentrated attentiveness being advocated here. Suppose the cared for individual is lost, due to death, separation or just growing up and leaving home? How does the attentive carer deal with this? Tronto suggests that the carer needs to find a place somewhere between the aloof, detached self and the emptied out, engulfed self, to maintain caring relations which are not everything to the carer.
Question: Both these issues raise pretty serious questions for an ethics of caring. Do you think they undermine it? Or do they, rather, help to clarify how an ethics of care should operate?
In this second section, Tronto raises a series of other important issues concerning caring (though it should be said that she raises more than she answers!) She points out that caring relations may have features atypical of the kinds of ethical issues found in more traditional accounts of ethics. For instance:
This can set up a power relationship (where there is even the possibility that the carer will want to maintain the dependent relationship.)
These issues are, again, difficult ones, and Tronto, having raised them, passes on fairly quickly. But you might want to look at them more closely. For instance:
What might the moral significance of dependence be? Does it make a difference whether you have created the dependence or not? (for instance, in having a child or breeding a pet you have created a dependent relationship; but you are not responsible for the state of your bed-ridden elderly mother).
Reading Tip Alistair Macintyre’s book Dependent Rational Animals develops some of these ideas, and thinks about the moral significance of dependence in human life. |
The third area Tronto discusses is particularity. As we have already seen, one of the characteristics of more traditional ethics is universalisation: if one person should do something, so should anyone who finds themselves in that situation. Tronto maintains that this is not necessarily the case, coming up with instances where universal rules will not work unless they are so general as to become meaningless (or, though she doesn’t say this, so specific as to become particular!) (this position of hers works particularly against broadly Kantian thinking).
Though there are problems of this kind involved in acting
in accordance with rules, there are also difficulties in rejecting them
to rely on care – as Tronto acknowledges.
A central problem here is the possibility of a kind of ethical nepotism,
where one privileges those for whom one cares over those for whom one
doesn’t. Tronto talks with some concern about the position of Nel
Noddings here. Noddings sees caring as:
For Tronto, these characteristics are troubling. She asks, quite rightly, about the social context of these caring encounters and relationships: how it comes to be, socially that one might encounter particular people, and what, indeed, about those people one never encounters, and for whom nobody cares?
This
raises what I think are some of the most difficult questions for an ethics
of care.
Let’s spend a bit of time thinking about this. Let’s take
the question:
In what ways could an ethics of care deal with the question of needy, distant strangers?
If we consider an ethics of care as we have so far looked at it, we find a focus on caring for individuals with whom we relate, and towards whom, perhaps, we have responsibilities. But what about people whom we will never meet? Or, indeed, people we choose not to meet? For instance, we might live in a city with a very poor neighbourhood; if we went there we might encounter people and feel some sort of responsibility to care; but by never going we can avoid encounter, and thus never get entangled in any caring responsibility.
A number of possible strategies could be adopted by an advocate of an ethics of care at this point. They could say:
Hungry people in distant countries, and impoverished communities in my own are political and social issues. They may raise moral questions too, but these generally fall out of the purview of an ethics of care, which primarily relates to the personal, not the public sphere.
Such a response might go on to suggest that a justice perspective (such as one based on utilitarian or human rights principles) would clearly be the best way to tackle such a question. A response of this type, then, would be confining an ethics of care to a particular place in the sphere of possible ethical theories: an ethics for dealing with personal questions. It would be adopting a view perfectly compatible with the non-universalism of much feminist thinking, by suggesting that in the world of moral theories, it’s “horses for courses”, and whilst an ethics of care is appropriate in personal situations, in the public, political sphere, justice is more appropriate. One can switch between theories, depending on the moral issue.
Of course, this raises meta-ethical questions about pluralism in moral theories, which it is perhaps not appropriate to go into here. Suffice it to note that this view would be resisted by many ethicists of care, who want to assign caring a wider moral role. As Tronto suggests towards the end of her article, such an approach could have the effect of “adding-on” a bit of extra caring as a corrective to morality (understood as being about justice, and according to feminist ethicists, as we have seen, fundamentally male-oriented). Bt the responses of ethicists who want to broaden the scope of caring could take at least two different forms:
As characterised by Tronto in the article we have been looking at, moral questions of this kind can be fitted into the personal sphere. Tronto summarises this (perhaps a bit brusquely!) by saying “for Noddings, this problem is solved by saying that because everyone will be cared for by someone, it is not anyone else’s concern to wonder about who is caring for whom in society” (p.353). So if there are people distant from us who need caring for but are not being cared for, it is the dereliction of someone else’s responsibility, not our own to take on. If everyone did all the caring for which was their responsibility, everyone who needed caring for would be cared for! Thus Noddings limits the zone of caring – which does mean that no-one is responsible for taking the cares of the world onto their shoulders - but which also seems to deny altogether a public sphere for morality.
Question:
Do you think Nodding’s response is adequate?
If so, why? If not, why not?
A “public relationship” response
A second kind of response – one to which Tronto herself moves towards – is what I call a “public relationship” response – that is to say, working from the basis that relationships or (interpreted in a broad sense) encounters need not necessarily be personal. Tronto comments that Noddings:
“ignores the ways in which the modern world is intertwined and the ways in which hundreds of prior public and private decisions affect where we find ourselves and which strangers show up at our doors”. (p.353)
For instance, one might not ever have a face to face encounter with a hungry child working on a cocoa plantation in West Africa.. But one does buy chocolate. And thus, through a strong of public and private decisions, one does have a kind of relationship with the child – a sort of encounter. Similarly, one may not meet the people who inhabit the impoverished part of town – but one does participate in and vote within a political and social system with particular policies on education, housing, taxation, transport and unemployment. In another sense, then a public relationship is set up. And this entails a kind of caring – and it is, I think, a caring for as well as a caring about. But its implications for how one lives are somewhat different to the more immediate caring Noddings envisages – tending for one’s family, neighbours and friends. It sees caring for as manifesting itself in a range of actions: what one consumes, where one works, how one travels, how one votes. This kind of response circumvents the problem with which Tronto is concerned, and which she sees manifest in Noddings’ work - of using caring as “an excuse to narrow the scope of our moral activity”.
Questions: Does this broader interpretation of caring work? For instance, can one be attentive to the needs of those whom one never meets? Or would justice do the same work and do it better?
Tronto returns at the end of her article to worry again at the gender issues bound up with caring.
She says, very bluntly that she can make the generalization that men care about and women care for in this society. Do you agree with her insistence on this point?
She expresses her anxiety about the gendering of caring for as feminine, suggesting that the attentiveness involved “may be a reflection of a survival mechanism for women or others who are dealing with oppressive conditions, rather than a quality of intrinsic value on its own” (p.354); reflecting service and deferentiality. What do you think she has in mind here? Is it a really telling criticism of caring?
Tronto wants to distinguish between a feminine and a feminist account, where a feminist account asks broader social and political questions and contextualises caring within them. Do you think this is possible? Does she end just where the hard questions start getting asked – like what does this mean in practice?
I want to end thinking about an ethics of care by posing a couple of further questions, and adding a quotation.
And the quotation, from a more recent paper by Carol Gilligan:
“Theoretically, the distinction between justice and care cuts across the familiar divisions between thinking and feeling, egoism and altruism, theoretical and practical reasoning. It call attention to the fact that all relationships, public and private can be characterised in terms both of equality and in terms of attachment. And that both inequality and detachment constitute grounds for moral concern. Since everyone is vulnerable both to oppression and abandonment, two moral visions – one of justice and one of care – recur in human experience”. Gilligan, Carol (1994) “Moral Orientation and Moral Development” in May and Sharratt (eds) Applied Ethics (NJ: Prentice Hall) p.262
As we all know, many ethical issues are highly contentious. Issues ranging from euthanasia to vegetarianism, from the treatment of asylum seekers to the taking of illegal drugs are debated daily in moral terms in the popular press. In grappling with almost any ethical problem in, say, medical or environmental ethics there are bound to be a number of strongly held views put forward by those from different interest groups or with different social, cultural or religious perspectives. Furthermore, there are almost certainly moral voices which are being suppressed, squeezed out of public discussion. How should one deal with such ethical situations?
Now read Alison Jaggar’s article “Towards a Feminist Conception of Moral Reasoning” in Sterba p.356-374 |
Jagger considers some ways of approaching these issues by means of what she calls FPD or Feminist Practical Dialogue. So what we will be looking at in the last section of this part of the module on feminist ethics is a feminist way into thinking about ethical dialogue involving those whose views are ethically divergent and those whose voices are often not heard.
First, then, we should ask what makes this specifically feminist. In answer to this question, Jaggar says it’s not that its been developed by feminists, nor that women are, culturally, more likely to engage in dialogue than men (though both might be the case!) Rather, it is because it is an ethical dialogue that has a “distinctively feminist commitment to ending women’s subordination”. Of course, this isn’t an essential part of ethical dialogue, but we will be thinking about this distinctively feminist version.
Jaggar identifies a number of characteristics of ethical dialogue which have emerged from a variety of feminist settings. Some of these are as follows:
She suggests that consensus agreements are particularly valued in such dialogic contexts (rather than, for instance, majority votes, or decisions being steamrollered through).
Questions: How do you react to these characteristics of moral dialogue? Do you think they are obvious – and clichéd? (Think how often we hear politicians beginning a sentence with “With respect…” – are they abusing the term?) Or do you think they are vague and unhelpful; or, perhaps; leading to interminable debates that never come to any conclusion because those engaged in them will never agree, but never act to impose their will on others?
Jaggar moves on (p.360-361) to describe practices of feminist pedagogy, arguing that it’s important to create a sense of community in the classroom to get dialogue really going. These include “not only an attentive ear, but food, drink, haircuts and hugs”.
Question: Would you like that sort of classroom (or virtual classroom?) Do you really think it helps with learning? Is what Jaggar suggests possible within the formal context of higher education, for instance?
Jaggar then brings these different techniques together into a more formal account of feminist practical dialogue.
Read Jaggar’s account on p. 362-369 carefully.
Before reading my summary, write down what you think are the key characteristics of FPD as Jaggar presents them.
My summary suggests that the following are of central significance:
1) First person narrative, where contributors can recount
their own experience in their own terms allowing others to encounter very
different lives and ways of viewing the world;
2) Allowing such personal reflections to become part of collective reflection,
where there are “counterstories” and reinterpretation of experiences;
3) Trying to include diverse perspectives from people of different ages,
classes, races etc – especially those who are “on the fringes”
of society who may be especially affected by discrimination, and whose
voices are rarely heard;
4) Including emotions as part of moral discussion, rather than exclusively
relying on abstract rules or principles;
5) The practice of virtues including responsibility, self-discipline,
sensitivity, respect and trust – as well as good will, and effort.
6) Trying to see and hear what other people are really saying
7) Placing the dialogue within the context of striving for friendship
and caring, as a discussion between concrete individuals
8) Approaching dialogue not as a battle, or “adversarial debate”
but as a co-operative and nurturing enterprise
9) Emphasising the importance of listening as well as speaking
10) Aiming at consensus, even where this proves unattainable.
Some further questions about FPD
1. Jaggar herself raises the question whether competitiveness
and critical questioning might produce moral reflection more effectively
than nurture and co-operation. She attempts to counter this view, but
do you think the countering is effective?
2. Do you think there are some contexts where this kind of discussion
would be more appropriate than others? (if so, suggest some more/less
effective contexts). Or do you think all moral discussion should approximate
to this – or no moral discussion should approximate to this?! Try
to explain why you hold your view. NB: In answering this question, you
may want to think about context a) in terms of the setting of the moral
discussion (eg on the radio or tv, in a letters column in a newspaper,
in a meeting of the local council, in a local residents meeting, in a
university seminar…) and b) in terms of the people who might be
involved (for instance, a debate about medical ethics where representatives
of powerful drugs companies are present; a debate about abortion with
both pro-life and pro-abortion campaigners in the room as well as women
who have just had, or decided not to have abortions).
3. Imagine that you are in charge of organising a local debate about a
proposal to build a bypass through a rural area. Would you implement any
of the ideas of FPD? If so, which? If not, why not?
4. Jaggar concludes her article by pointing out what she considers to
be some of the major advantages of FPD: its concrete origin in activism
rather than an academic’s head; its respect for women’s moral
autonomy, experience and insights (and thus its feminist nature) and its
operation within a context of care for particular others; and its pragmatic
optimism. Do you think these are all strengths? Or might they (or some
of them) turn out to hinder any process of moral decision-making? Do you
think this process really is as practical as Jaggar maintains?
In this section, we have examined:
1) The beginnings of feminist ethics in the work of Carol
Gilligan, with her emphasis on two moral voices, the voice of justice
and the voice of care;
2) Feminist criticisms of traditional ethics for lack of interest in women’s
concerns and moral experience, emphasis on rationality, universalisability,
emphasis on autonomy, separate individuals, and generally overvaluing
culturally male moral experience;
3) Developments in feminist ethics, including feminine ethics, maternal
ethics, lesbian ethics and political ethics;
4) Baier’s text on thinking about women and moral theory, and specifically
on the importance of appropriate trust;
5) Tronto’s discussion of caring; her gendered distinction between
caring for and caring about; difficulties raised by ideas about caring;
questions about dependence and about caring for needy strangers; different
ideas of the scope of caring as a moral theory;
6) Jaggar’s account of feminist practical dialogue (FPD) ; how to
go about conducting moral discussions co-operatively and aiming at consensus;
the difficulties and drawbacks of FPD
In this discussion of feminist ethics I hope to have introduced some of the background to feminist ethics and some of the main ideas which dominate it today – both in terms of how feminists might construct moral theories (or, at least, how they might approach ethics) the particular case of an ethics of care; and one way in which feminists might approach moral discussion where there are different and dissenting voices.